|
|
|
Machan's Musings - Slavery & Property - Communal vs. Individual Where modern liberals falter is in their refusal to recognize that individual liberties and rights are virtually meaningless if one does not have the right to property, to freely obtain, hold, and trade goods and services. If another person may not own me, what good is this if my assets and earnings may be taken from me without my permission? Say I am a very talented musician and other people value what I might do with this talent. If they may coerce me into producing music for them, in what sense am I not a slave? If I do produce my music and earn income from this, but others may take these earnings from me, again in what sense am I free? Yet in contemporary academic moral, political, and legal circles there is a very influential movement arguing exactly this: one’s assets and one’s earnings belong to society, not to oneself. Such thinkers as Professors Liam Murphy, Thomas Nagel, Cass Sunstein, Stephen Holmes and many others believe that when government taxes us, it merely retakes what belongs to it and we have nothing to complain about. Private property rights do not exist. (Murphy and Nagel lay all this out in The Myth of Ownership, a book prominently published by Oxford University Press in 2002, and Sunstein and Holmes advance their similar idea in The Cost of Rights, published in 1999 by another prestigious house, W. W. Norton. And the very famous late Harvard philosophy professor John Rawls argued, in his A Theory of Justice [Harvard University Press, 1971], that since one does not always deserve one’s assets and belongings, these may be redistributed to others with moral and legal impunity!) That this is a rank reactionary idea should be very clear to anyone who has some notion of the political theory of feudalism which had maintained that the king owns everything, even most of the people, within the realm he rules. It is also the thesis of Communism, whereby the people as a whole own everything—one reason why East German border guards saw nothing wrong with murdering citizens of that country who tried to escape by climbing over the Berlin Wall; after all, they were thieves who were stealing the labor power of the society! Given how enthusiastic modern Liberals are about raising taxation so they can distribute the resulting revenue as they deem proper, why do they get away with the ruse of being fierce opponents of slavery, of unjust discrimination? How did these people manage to intimidate their political opponents and much of the public with their holier than thou attitude, as if it those who resist taxation, who want to give the money taken from people back to those people, as the bad guys? The reason is that while these "democratic liberals" oppose individual slavery—an individual master owning slaves—they see nothing wrong with collective slavery. The community, for most communitarians—led by the likes of the Canadian Charles Taylor and the American Amitai Etzioni—has the just authority to confiscated the assets and earnings of its members and do with them as "the community" will. (This, of course, means that some individuals in the community will have such authority!) That is to say, collective slavery is fine with these folks, at least up to some arbitrary point. Like the East Germany communists, these communitarians believe that people belong to the community—not in the sense of voluntarily belonging to a club from which one may withdraw but in the sense in which my arm belongs to me. On the way toward defending this collectivist idea of slavery, these political and legal theorists argue voraciously that individualism is evil by promoting the pitting of all human beings against one another, and of pretending that human individuals are able to flourish without their fellows, without cooperating with others. Of course, no individualist has ever argued this. What individualists have argued, for the most part, is that to secure the cooperation of human beings, one must ask for but never conscript it. Individualists see people as sovereign agents, self-governors, who do, however, often benefit from the cooperation of others. They do not believe, however, that these others may be enslaved, either by other individuals or by the society. The idea that property should be collectively owned is in fact the main step toward endorsing slavery. That’s really quite elementary. Discuss this Article (4 messages) |