Bill, I wrote, " . . . the standard of life is not just their life, but the life proper to man qua man . . ." And you replied, "Properly understood, there is no contradiction here. The life proper to man is simply a guide to sustaining and preserving one's own life." But we are talking about a set of principles and values which might not be understood properly. And whether or not there is a disagreement, we know that contradictions can't exist. And if a person has a right to X, there can be no such thing as another person having a right to violate that right. It would become a self-contradicting sentence that would render the concept of rights meaningless. The life proper to man is not "simply a guide to sustaining and preserving one's own life." First, it goes beyond sustaining and presevering to include flourishing. Second, it is the source for deriving that set of values and principles that will be common to all men. Then from that set of values and principles, individuals apply them to their concrete circumstances and individual preferences. In the case of individual rights, they are a set of moral principles that preserve the ability to live among other men. If that isn't accepted, then, because it is the very foundation of moral values in any potential interaction with others, one can't have any claim to any rights of their own. Just as with any fundamental value, it is derived from human nature, and thus applies to all men. If someone chose to say that they had reasoned from the concept of their individual life, (e.g., "I am alive. If I have a right to my life, then I have the right to that which it requires..." etc.) and then went on to say that they extrapolate this to all men, they still end up in the same place. That is that they cannot avoid this contradiction if they claim a right to do something (to preserve their life), yet it requires that they violate the rights of someone else. If moral rights exist and are objective they can't belong to one person and not to another. (There can be circumstances where a person voluntarily relinquishes their rights - like commiting a murder - but they can't claim that their right to sustain their life somehow entitles them to take away someone elses life under anything but self-defense.) ------------ You said, "One's own life (not the lives of others) is still the purpose to which that standard is to be applied." Sort of. It is actually your happiness that is your purpose, and being alive is a precondition. But you are correct that it is yours and not others that is the focus of your purpose. However you can't say any action you might claim is needed to stay alive (or happy) is justified, ie., moral, if it violates the right of another. Because I have the purpose of being happy, and because I have the right to not be subject to the initiation of force, threat of force, fraud or theft, doesn't add up to saying that I have the right to violate someone elses rights. -------------- You wrote: Under normal life-sustaining conditions, it is ethical and moral to respect the lives of others because it is in one's self-interest to do so.
It certainly is in ones self-interest to respect objectively derived moral values and ethical principles. And it is the integration and application of those principles that make life proper to man possible - for each individual. But the phrasing you used allows for a strange dichotomy. It implies that pragmatism is at the heart of making decisions regarding the principles, and that anytime I reason that my self-interest would be served by sacrificing someone else, then all that is needed is to point at some conditions that fail to meet the criteria of "normal life sustaining" and I would get to be moral, retain my integrity, violate no principles, but sacrifice an innocent. In fact, you don't "have the right to your life" technically speaking, what you have a right to is to not be subjected to the initiation of force, threat of force, fraud or theft, and in exchange you are obliged by logic and justice to not use those against anyone else. If others are not interfering with you, then you get to take all the actions needed to pursue your life EXCEPT for those you don't have a right to take. You went on to say: However, there are circumstances in which normal conditions of survival do not obtain and in which one is morally justified in sacrificing other human beings in order to save one's own life. Lifeboat conditions are one; war is another.
I don't agree. Lifeboat conditions, as I pointed out, are not deserving of serious discussion. I could create an imaginary situation that would make anyone uncomfortable, no matter which side of this discussion they are on. They are just rhetorical tricks and don't help us understanding these principles. As to war, as I said before, I'm not sure how to resolve the apparent contradiction. But I don't take my intellectual fumbling in this area as a sign that up might be down, right might be left, or that rights might be non-rights. ------------------ You wrote: The Israelis targeted the weapons of Hamas for the sake of their own self-defense and self-preservation even though they knew that innocent Palestinians would be killed in the process. Yes, the blood of those innocents fell on Hamas, but the reason it did is that the Israelis had a moral right to defend themselves. What was the alternative? Suicide -- the deliberate sacrifice of their own lives in order to spare the lives of innocent civilians.
I agree. And in this instance, the deaths were caused by Hamas and the Israelies didn't violate rights. But I still fumble about when trying to get a better grasp of where the line is drawn here. If the Israelies had the capacity to drive every single person in the Gaza strip into the sea - till they all drown - would that still fit the justification that we both agree was adequate to the actions they actually took? It gets complicated. If they stop too soon, they are just giving Hamas room to breath and rearm and stopping too soon will end up costing their lives (i.e., inadequate self-defense), but is there a point they could go to that would break the spirit of support for Hamas so that it would not be a threat to future loss of Israelie lives? And is that point the defining line to be achieved. If so, then the next step is to see which tactics would take them to that point with the least loss of Israelie lives, and within that condition, the least loss of non-enemy residents of Gaza. We have laws that attempt to define the parameters of self-defense on an individual basis. Was the attack substantial? Life threatening? If it was a threat, was it something that a reasonable man would take serious? Was it imminent? Could it have been safely defused without the use of violence or loss? Etc. But we don't appear to have a set of commonly applied rules for determining what is proper for national self-defense. --------------- Our own military rules of engagement prevent soldiers from killing unarmed civilians who may also be scouts or informers for the enemy.
We need to have civilian control of the military for obvious reasons, but when those politicians in control are vote hungery, dishonest, unprincipled asses (as we have now), then they set rules of engagement that make no sense anywhere but in their befuddled poll-taking-is-truth-and-justice psychoepistemology. Terrorism is particularly attrocious because of this method of hiding among and using of civilians. It is why terrorism needs to be fought more vigorously and especially against those who make it possible by funding, supporting, providing cover, trading with, etc. And we need a better set of rules such that if we declare war against a terrorist group, we have to declare war against any nation whose government supports them. Clearly we can't join the terrorists in abandoning the principles of discriminating between those who are innocent and those are enemies. But I certainly don't have enough answers to be happy at this point.
|