About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3


Sanction: 4, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 4, No Sanction: 0
Post 60

Monday, August 7, 2006 - 11:53pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
William, you made my day! Glad to see you back here doing your shtick! Wonderful stuff, as usual. Perhaps, just perhaps, the explanation is:

Hell hath no fury like a neo-Objectivist scorned!

Nah, that's too obvious. Must be something subtler at work here! ;-)

Sorry, I couldn't resist!

- The Other William Scott

Post 61

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 6:18amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
WSS said to Nick:
I don't think that hanging around bitching out people on O-lists is making you happy or adding to your life's pleasure or adding to the sum total of knowledge and grace in the world.
An astute observation brilliantly stated.


Sanction: 13, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 13, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 13, No Sanction: 0
Post 62

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 10:30amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Nick:

You think it is a relativist's position. You're gazing at the entirety of my thought from a description of a mental visualization and from me advising someone to go stand on his own ground and to trust his own mind. I have many, many mental visualizations, and that is just one of them; and you misunderstood what I was talking about anyway, by making assumptions that no one agreed to but you. I will tell you what I am: I'm a Jennaist. If you don't understand that, then whatever I say won't matter.

I'm not going to be drawn into your rhetorical cages so that you can "watch me reason my way out of them", because those cages are based on your assumptions, not mine. I choose not to be someone's victim by simply refusing to be where they want me. I can understand why Bridget was frustrated. So that's why I had to stop this before it started, because I also have read your posts and the way you operate.

I really have no idea what you want-- what is your goal? To know me better, or to watch me, or otheres, try to escape from your contraptions?

Yes, you didn't like my condescending tone. That's how it was for me to read your post on relativism, which seemed to come out of nowhere. I actually said, "What the hell? Where did that come from? What did I ever do to him?!"

I'll just diffuse this right now, and say that yes, I am a moral relativist-- but only at the speed of light:





Post 63

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 11:04amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hey, WWS, Jenna is the one who cried foul first, just because I said she seemed like a relativst.  If that's enough for her to feel victimized by the nasty-Otani, Gee, she gives me a lot of power. Not bad for a prickley, argumentative jerk.

bis bald,

Nick


Post 64

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 11:13amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
You think it is a relativist's position. You're gazing at the entirety of my thought from a description of a mental visualization and from me advising someone to go stand on his own ground and to trust his own mind. I have many, many mental visualizations, and that is just one of them; and you misunderstood what I was talking about anyway, by making assumptions that no one agreed to but you. I will tell you what I am: I'm a Jennaist. If you don't understand that, then whatever I say won't matter.
Well, no, I'm not gazng at the entirety of your thought. But if your other visualizations conflict with the raltivistic ones, then your thought cannot be very coherent, and that's more than just a perspective.

bis bald,

Nick


Post 65

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 11:25amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill:
Oh, so you're claiming that I'm shouting all the time, simply because I use a larger font than others. Cal, that's hilarious! I use a larger font, because I find it easier to read and more pleasing to the eye -- at least to mine.
A strange argument - the only text that would be easier to read then are your own contributions, and then only after they've been posted. A more rational method would be to use a larger font in your browser, so that all texts would be easier to read. For example with Opera you have only to hit the + key to zoom in and get a bigger text, but even primitive browsers like IE must have some option to get bigger letters.
No, the meaning of "truth" is correspondence with reality. A proposition is true if and only if it corresponds to reality. Ask any decent philosopher. Its correspondence is eternal, because it doesn't change with a change in our knowledge. If a proposition is discovered not to have corresponded to reality, even though we thought that it did, then it never did correspond. It didn't suddenly fail to correspond when we discovered that it failed to. Similarly, if it's discovered to have corresponded to reality even though we thought that it didn't, then it always did correspond. It didn't suddenly come to correspond when we discovered that it did.
With that definition "truth" is unknowable, as you would have to be omniscient to be able to know whether your proposition really corresponds to reality. Such a Platonic abstraction is of course completely impractical, therefore we settle for a more pragmatic definition based on a sufficiently high probability. We suppose that our "pragmatic truth" does correspond to your "ideal truth", but we can't be sure, as we are not omniscient. We'll just have to live with that. The "ideal truth" is indeed eternal, but unknowable, while the "pragmatic truth" is knowable, but may not be eternal. At a certain moment a "pragmatic truth" may be turned into a "pragmatic falsity", when there is enough evidence that this "pragmatic truth" does not correspond to the "ideal truth", and so on.
Here I don't agree. If all the evidence supports a scientific conclusion and none contradicts it, then there is nothing tentative about the conclusion. The term "tentative" implies that the conclusion is provisional -- that it awaits further confirmation.
No, I mean by "tentative" that we can't be 100% certain that the conclusion is correct, as we are not omniscient.
But if all the evidence supports the conclusion and none contradicts it, then no further confirmation is, or can be, forthcoming. In that case, the conclusion is not tentative but certain.
It's very well possible that at that time no further confirmation is or can be forthcoming. So we may then call our conclusion "true" in the pragmatical sense, but we can never know if the conclusion is true in the ideal sense.


So what do you think: did the scientists at the time of Young and Fresnel have reason to doubt the truth of their proposition?

Not that I am aware, in which case, they could not in logic have recognized the possibility that they were mistaken.
Was their conclusion then true or false?

Post 66

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 12:03pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Nick:

My visualizations don't conflict. They integrate.

Re: Your relativist post, I mirrored your tone of voice, made it stronger, and gave it back to you.

Judging only from your posts with Bridget and on OL (as I have no idea what the rest of your life is like), your modus operandi on forums generally does not appeal to me.

I'm dropping this, and no, I'm not taking this as seriously or as personally as you think I am. I just know that I choose my battles.
(Edited by Jenna W
on 8/08, 12:09pm)


Post 67

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 12:52pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I'm dropping this, and no, I'm not taking this as seriously or as personally as you think I am. I just know that I choose my battles.

 
Okay, whatever.

bis bald,

Nick


Post 68

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 11:54pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I wrote, "Oh, so you're claiming that I'm shouting all the time, simply because I use a larger font than others. Cal, that's hilarious! I use a larger font, because I find it easier to read and more pleasing to the eye -- at least to mine." Cal replied,
A strange argument - the only text that would be easier to read then are your own contributions, and then only after they've been posted. A more rational method would be to use a larger font in your browser, so that all texts would be easier to read. For example with Opera you have only to hit the + key to zoom in and get a bigger text, but even primitive browsers like IE must have some option to get bigger letters.
Thanks for the suggestion. But I wasn't doing it only for my benefit; I thought that others might appreciate it as well. In any case, I don't use a larger font, because I want everything I say to be construed as shouting, which is a bizarre suggestion! I use it because I find it more esthetically pleasing and would hope that others do as well. It's simply a personal preference.

I wrote, "No, the meaning of 'truth' is correspondence with reality. A proposition is true if and only if it corresponds to reality. Ask any decent philosopher. Its correspondence is eternal, because it doesn't change with a change in our knowledge. If a proposition is discovered not to have corresponded to reality, even though we thought that it did, then it never did correspond. It didn't suddenly fail to correspond when we discovered that it failed to. Similarly, if it's discovered to have corresponded to reality even though we thought that it didn't, then it always did correspond. It didn't suddenly come to correspond when we discovered that it did."
With that definition "truth" is unknowable, as you would have to be omniscient to be able to know whether your proposition really corresponds to reality.
But that, you see, is precisely what I'm denying. I'm saying that it's a non-sequitur to infer that just because we erred in the past, we could therefore be in error now. In fact, our recognition of past error presupposes our present recognition of the truth, without which we couldn't legitimately say that we were in error.
Such a Platonic abstraction is of course completely impractical, therefore we settle for a more pragmatic definition based on a sufficiently high probability.
No, this is the wrong inference to draw, because it is based on a faulty premise, that past error necessarily implies the possibility of present error.
We suppose that our "pragmatic truth" does correspond to your "ideal truth", but we can't be sure, as we are not omniscient. We'll just have to live with that. The "ideal truth" is indeed eternal, but unknowable, while the "pragmatic truth" is knowable, but may not be eternal. At a certain moment a "pragmatic truth" may be turned into a "pragmatic falsity", when there is enough evidence that this "pragmatic truth" does not correspond to the "ideal truth", and so on.
Enough evidence? How would you know whether or not there is enough evidence that this "pragmatic truth" does not correspond to the "ideal truth", if you can never know what the ideal truth is anyway?!

I wrote, "If all the evidence supports a scientific conclusion and none contradicts it, then there is nothing tentative about the conclusion. The term 'tentative' implies that the conclusion is provisional -- that it awaits further confirmation."
No, I mean by "tentative" that we can't be 100% certain that the conclusion is correct, as we are not omniscient."
If you're going to say that there are no grounds for claiming 100% certainty, because we're not omniscient, then by the same token, there would also be no grounds for claiming 99% certainty versus (say) 89% or 79%? I can claim 50% certainty that a coin will land heads (or tails), only because I'm 100% certain that it must land either heads or tails. Knowledge, by definition, is 100% certainty. Before you can calibrate degrees of probability, you must have absolute certainty or absolute knowledge; otherwise, you cannot know whether a particular proposition is highly probable or highly improbable. Lacking such knowledge, you'd be in the position of claiming only that it's probable that a particular conclusion is probable. But then you'd have to say that the probability that it's probable is absolutely certain. Otherwise, you'd be reduced to saying that it's probable that it's probable that it's probable, and so on. In short, your probabilities have to be anchored to certainty. Otherwise, you're not justified in claiming anything to be true -- not even that something is 99% probable -- because you have nothing certain to hang it on. Nor would there be any genuine scientific discoveries, because you could never know whether or not you'd actually discovered something. Maybe it's not a genuine discovery after all; maybe it's just a mistaken identification. Nor could you say that it's even highly probably that the discovery is genuine. How do you know it's highly probable. What could "highly probable" even mean here?

I wrote, "But if all the evidence supports the conclusion and none contradicts it, then no further confirmation is, or can be, forthcoming. In that case, the conclusion is not tentative but certain." Cal replied,
It's very well possible that at that time no further confirmation is or can be forthcoming. So we may then call our conclusion "true" in the pragmatical sense, but we can never know if the conclusion is true in the ideal sense.
This is a bogus distinction. There is no "pragmatic" versus "ideal" truth. When I flip a coin into the air, I don't say that it's pragmatically true that there's a 50% chance it will land heads (or tails). I say it's true, period.
So what do you think: did the scientists at the time of Young and Fresnel have reason to doubt the truth of their proposition?
I replied, "Not that I am aware, in which case, they could not in logic have recognized the possibility that they were mistaken." To which Cal replied,
Was their conclusion then true or false?
It was false. Look, Cal, to say that, because they had no reason to doubt their conclusion, they were not justified in admitting the possibility of error, is not to say that they could not have been wrong. A person can have no reason to believe that he could be in error and yet be in error. Indeed, in order to be in error about one's beliefs, they must actually be one's beliefs. One cannot be in error about a belief, if one doesn't actually hold it as a belief, and if one believes that a particular proposition is true, then one cannot simultaneously admit that it could be false. I've made this point repeatedly throughout our dialogue, yet it's one that you've consistently failed to address. It is simply illogical to say, on the one hand, that your conclusion is true and, on the other hand, that it could be false, because a conclusion that is true cannot be false.

- Bill


Post 69

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 9:57amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jenna, great "Moral Relativity" diagram. Funny stuff!

Btw, how did you do that? I'm kind of computer illiterate, and can't seem to do anything like that with my Safari browser and "Gimpy Netscape text box." :-|

- Bill

Post 70

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 10:13amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill:

If you're asking how I linked to the comic's website using the image, I used the anchor tags and the image tags together, by enclosing the image tags with the anchor tags.

So it would look like this:

[a href="url"][img src="image.jpg"][/a]

except that the "[" and "]" would be "<" and ">" respectively (if I actually typed out the "<" and ">" the browser would read them as the real thing instead of as an example so I have to use "[" and "]" instead). I did do this on Firefox and Gimpy Netscape, too, and it always works. I hope that was clear...? :-)

Post 71

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 11:07amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jenna, that graph drops the other half of the Relativity Diagram. =)

What actually happens is that for any value greater than c the diagram is a mirror image, the amount of energy required (or extent of time dilation or lorentz contraction, etc) asymptotically approaches infinity at C, but falls off in the same manner both before and after C. Relativity forbids travelling *AT* c, but not less or more than it (it's just a problem getting through c to go >c) Interestingly, the implications on that side of the graph is that it requires less energy to go *faster* and more energy to slow down, similiarly at about 2c and above time dilation and lorentz contractions become negligable. Quantum tunneling may provide a way to get through the c barrier

So once one goes faster than c, they can get away with less and less rationalizations of their moral relativity ;)

Post 72

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 11:30amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill:
Thanks for the suggestion. But I wasn't doing it only for my benefit; I thought that others might appreciate it as well.
I don't think so, as no one else is following your example. Perhaps you can take it to a poll?
But that, you see, is precisely what I'm denying. I'm saying that it's a non-sequitur to infer that just because we erred in the past, we could therefore be in error now.
This is simply an example of induction: we have been so often erred in the past that it would be extremely unlikely that we now suddenly no longer will err. That doesn't mean that it isn't possible that we this time are really right - for all we know we got it finally right this time-, only that we never can be 100% certain. You claim 100% certainty, which you never can prove.
In fact, our recognition of past error presupposes our present recognition of the truth, without which we couldn't legitimately say that we were in error.
No, no, our present recognition of the "truth" is what I called the "pragmatic truth", that what to the best of our knowledge is the truth, but which is not necessarily the "real truth". We never can be sure that we've finally found the real truth, as we are not omniscient.
Enough evidence? How would you know whether or not there is enough evidence that this "pragmatic truth" does not correspond to the "ideal truth", if you can never know what the ideal truth is anyway?!
Sorry, my formulation was confusing - I meant to say that to the best of our knowledge there is enough evidence that was previously our pragmatic truth does not correspond to the real truth and that we now found what the real truth is. The catch is again "to the best of our knowledge" - we assume that we now know the real truth, but we must remain open to the possibility - no matter how infinitesimal it may seem now - that we're wrong. It's rather a waste of time to qualify our statements every time to admit that possibility as it always exists - it's a background we normally ignore - until we get new evidence that causes us to reconsider our previous conclusions.
If you're going to say that there are no grounds for claiming 100% certainty, because we're not omniscient, then by the same token, there would also be no grounds for claiming 99% certainty versus (say) 89% or 79%?
I don't claim that you can assign exact values for the degree of certainty of your conclusion - you should read these somewhat like: 50% certainty: may be true, but I'm not sure about it, 99% certainty: it's very probably true, etc. Such rough estimates can be based on the strength of the evidence that you have for your conclusion.
Nor would there be any genuine scientific discoveries, because you could never know whether or not you'd actually discovered something. Maybe it's not a genuine discovery after all; maybe it's just a mistaken identification.
Indeed, it has happened often enough that what once seemed to be a genuine discovery turned out to be wrong (and please don't start again that argument of how we can know now... etc. I've answered all that in my previous posts).
Nor could you say that it's even highly probably that the discovery is genuine. How do you know it's highly probable. What could "highly probable" even mean here?
That's the old strawman again: "if we can't 100% sure we can't know anything". This is a non sequitur.
This is a bogus distinction. There is no "pragmatic" versus "ideal" truth. When I flip a coin into the air, I don't say that it's pragmatically true that there's a 50% chance it will land heads (or tails). I say it's true, period.
Not at all. How sure are you that this is a "fair" coin? Small variations in form and or composition may influence the odds. Perhaps there is a 51% chance that it will land heads. You can only test that by flipping the coin many times. The more flips, the better the estimate of the true probability, but you'll have to flip it an infinite number of times to be 100% sure.
It was false. Look, Cal, to say that, because they had no reason to doubt their conclusion, they were not justified in admitting the possibility of error, is not to say that they could not have been wrong. A person can have no reason to believe that he could be in error and yet be in error.
This is really gibberish to me. If he can be in error, why should he have no reason to believe that he could be in error? That only shows that he has a firm grasp of reality. He realizes that even while all the evidence seems to point unambiguously to one conclusion and he therefore has to accept this conclusion, there always remains the possibility - how unlikely it may seem at that moment - that he is in error. Beware of people who think they can't err.
Indeed, in order to be in error about one's beliefs, they must actually be one's beliefs. One cannot be in error about a belief, if one doesn't actually hold it as a belief, and if one believes that a particular proposition is true, then one cannot simultaneously admit that it could be false.
Of course one can. Only a dogmatist thinks that he can't be wrong. Any realist is aware of the fact that he is convinced that a certain proposition is true is no guarantee that it is really true.
I've made this point repeatedly throughout our dialogue, yet it's one that you've consistently failed to address. It is simply illogical to say, on the one hand, that your conclusion is true and, on the other hand, that it could be false, because a conclusion that is true cannot be false.
And I have answered this point repeatedly throughout our dialogue, so I see no point in repeating it here for the n-th time.


Post 73

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 7:08pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I wrote, "In fact, our recognition of past error presupposes our present recognition of the truth, without which we couldn't legitimately say that we're in error."
No, no, our present recognition of the "truth" is what I called the "pragmatic truth", that what to the best of our knowledge is the truth, but which is not necessarily the "real truth".
But that distinction is itself based on the argument that past error presupposes the possibility of present error, which in turn is based on the recognition that it really is true (not just "pragmatically true") that your past conclusions are in error. If you're going to base your distinction between pragmatic truth and real truth on that argument, then you can't assume the distinction as part of the argument itself. Otherwise, you're begging the question. To properly make that argument, you have to acknowledge that the conclusion that your past conclusions were in error is really true, not just pragmatically true. Then, assuming the argument to be valid, you can make the distinction between real truth and pragmatic truth. However, as you know, it is my contention that since the argument isn't valid, the distinction isn't either.

I wrote, "Enough evidence? How would you know whether or not there is enough evidence that this 'pragmatic truth' does not correspond to the 'ideal truth', if you can never know what the ideal truth is anyway?!" Cal replied,
Sorry, my formulation was confusing - I meant to say that to the best of our knowledge there is enough evidence that was previously our pragmatic truth does not correspond to the real truth and that we now found what the real truth is.
Huh?? This formulation is even more confusing. What are you trying to say here?
The catch is again "to the best of our knowledge" - we assume that we now know the real truth, but we must remain open to the possibility - no matter how infinitesimal it may seem now - that we're wrong.
But why do you "assume" that you know the real truth, if (according to you) the real truth can never be known? What grounds do you have to make that assumption? And what, on your epistemology, could it mean to say that the possibility that you're wrong is "infinitesmal"?? Infinitesmal, relative to what standard of knowledge? It can't be omniscience, because you couldn't calculate probabilities based on a deviation from omniscience.
It's rather a waste of time to qualify our statements every time to admit that possibility as it always exists - it's a background we normally ignore - until we get new evidence that causes us to reconsider our previous conclusions.
Why would new evidence cause you to reconsider your previous conclusions, if you don't consider it to be knowledge? Would someone's arbitrary assertions cause you to reconsider your previous conclusions? No, because you don't consider them to be knowledge or to have any bearing on your previous conclusions. So why would "evidence" that you don't consider to be real knowledge, because it could be illusory or misleading, have any rational bearing on your previous conclusions?

I wrote, "If you're going to say that there are no grounds for claiming 100% certainty, because we're not omniscient, then by the same token, there would also be no grounds for claiming 99% certainty versus (say) 89% or 79%?" Cal replied,
I don't claim that you can assign exact values for the degree of certainty of your conclusion - you should read these somewhat like: 50% certainty: may be true, but I'm not sure about it, 99% certainty: it's very probably true, etc. Such rough estimates can be based on the strength of the evidence that you have for your conclusion.
But don't you see, the "strength" of the evidence assumes that such evidence constitutes knowledge -- that it is evidence of actual facts. If you can't know any actual facts for certain, because, as you claim, you're not omniscient, then on what grounds would any new "evidence" have a bearing either for or against your previous conclusions?

I wrote, "Nor would there be any genuine scientific discoveries, because you could never know whether or not you'd actually discovered something. Maybe it's not a genuine discovery after all; maybe it's just a mistaken identification." Cal replied,
Indeed, it has happened often enough that what once seemed to be a genuine discovery turned out to be wrong (and please don't start again that argument of how we can know now... etc. I've answered all that in my previous posts).
So, then, you can't say it's a genuine discovery, right? And if it's not a genuine discovery, then how could it possibly count as evidence one way or the other?

I wrote, "Nor could you say that it's even highly probably that the discovery is genuine. How do you know it's highly probable. What could 'highly probable' even mean here?"
That's the old strawman again: "if we can't 100% sure we can't know anything". This is a non sequitur.
What I'm saying is that in order to know that a proposition is true, you have to be 100% certain of it; otherwise, your conclusion doesn't constitute knowledge. But if, as you seem to be saying, empirical propositions are never 100% certain, because we're not omniscient, then the empirical evidence that you claim has a bearing on your conclusions cannot qualify as reliable either, because you can't be sure of its authenticity.

I wrote, "There is no 'pragmatic' versus 'ideal' truth. When I flip a coin into the air, I don't say that it's pragmatically true that there's a 50% chance it will land heads (or tails). I say it's true, period."

Cal replied,
Not at all. How sure are you that this is a "fair" coin? Small variations in form and or composition may influence the odds. Perhaps there is a 51% chance that it will land heads. You can only test that by flipping the coin many times. The more flips, the better the estimate of the true probability, but you'll have to flip it an infinite number of times to be 100% sure.
All we mean when we say that there's a 50% chance that a coin will land heads (or tails) is that we have no reason to believe that it is any more likely to land on one side than on the other. And in the case of a standard coin, this is true; it is absolutely true, not just "pragmatically" true. In reality, of course, the coin's trajectory is governed by the laws of physics. If we could determine the precise force that is applied to it and the path that it will take and knew that it would land heads, then we wouldn't say that its probability of doing so is 50%; we'd say it's 100%, because we would know how it's going to land. Similarly, if we knew that the coin was weighted, we would have more knowledge about it than if we didn't know this. So, in that case, the probability of its landing heads (assuming it were weighted on the tail side) would be greater than 50%, because our knowledge of the coin is greater. Probabilities refer to our lack of knowledge about the occurrence of an event, not to its occurrence independently of our knowledge. So if the coin is weighted, but we are not aware of this and believe it to be fair, then we can still say that the probability of it's landing heads is 50% and that our statement is absolutely true, because what that statement means is that we have no reason to believe that the coin is more likely to land on one side than on the other, which is true: we don't.

I wrote, "It was false. Look, Cal, to say that, because they had no reason to doubt their conclusion, they were not justified in admitting the possibility of error, is not to say that they could not have been wrong. A person can have no reason to believe that he could be in error and yet be in error." Cal replied,
This is really gibberish to me. If he can be in error, why should he have no reason to believe that he could be in error?
Because there's nothing to indicate that he could be. Again, the fact that he erred in the past is not an indication that he could be in error now. I've made mistakes in arithmetic in the past. Does it follow from that that the arithmetic I'm doing now could be mistaken? I've made errors of identification before. Does it follow from that that any identification I make could be in error? No and no.
That only shows that he has a firm grasp of reality.
Wait a minute! I thought you said that we could never have a firm grasp of reality, because we're not omniscient.
He realizes that even while all the evidence seems to point unambiguously to one conclusion and he therefore has to accept this conclusion, there always remains the possibility - how unlikely it may seem at that moment - that he is in error. Beware of people who think they can't err.
We have to distinguish here between the possibility of error involving snap judgments, opinions and tentative conclusions, and the possibility of error involving propositions of which the person is fully convinced. If a person firmly believes that a proposition is true (e.g., that the earth is round), then it makes no sense for him to say that he could nevertheless be mistaken about it, simply because people have been mistaken about such things in the past.

I wrote, "Indeed, in order to be in error about one's beliefs, they must actually be one's beliefs. One cannot be in error about a belief, if one doesn't actually hold it as a belief, and if one believes that a particular proposition is true, then one cannot simultaneously admit that it could be false."
Of course one can. Only a dogmatist thinks that he can't be wrong. Any realist is aware of the fact that he is convinced that a certain proposition is true is no guarantee that it is really true.
Well, if he's convinced that it's true, then he already believes that he has that guarantee; otherwise, he wouldn't be convinced. I'm convinced that the earth is round, because I believe that the truth of that proposition is guaranteed by the evidence. More to the point: how do you reconcile the two statements:

(1) "X is true," and
(2) "X could be false."

I don't see these as compatible. Do you? The statement "X is true" precludes X being false. If X is true, then it cannot be false, whereas the statement "X could be false" does not preclude X being false. The latter statement (2) allows for the possibility that X actually is false, whereas the former (1) does not, since a proposition cannot be both true and false. So, if I'm convinced that X is true, then I cannot in logic believe simultaneously that it could be false.

- Bill
(Edited by William Dwyer
on 8/09, 7:14pm)

(Edited by William Dwyer
on 8/09, 7:33pm)


Post 74

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 7:44pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Jenna,

Thanks. I'll add these to my html codes. Maybe at some point I'll get a chance to use them.

- Bill

Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3


User ID Password or create a free account.