About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Forward one pageLast Page


Post 80

Saturday, October 15, 2011 - 10:23pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
P,

I think I agree with you.

Going back to the harmony of interests, let's say that we were trying to come up with a moral means of implementing the harmony of interests. We could say that you have a moral protection (a moral claim) against an initiation of force. Let's call that moral claim against an initiation of force a "right." Now, we could also try to go ahead and say that you have a moral claim against any kind of intentional use of force in any kind of context -- which would include having a moral claim against even retaliatory force, even when judiciously and objectively applied in the name of justice! If we did that, if we tried to say that rights involve moral protection (having a moral claim) against a moral judgment (judicious punishment/justice), then we would be contradicting ourselves.

It would essentially be a right to be "not guilty" for your committed crimes. Instead of being a means toward implementing the harmony of interests, it would end up destroying any possibility of harmony. Refraining from judging evil -- because your moral code implies that the evil have a "right" to escape judgment -- would be a disaster.

Now, here is where it gets tricky. There is an amendment we can make that might allow us to get away with the notion that rights are moral protections from any kind of intentional use of force. The amendment would be that we would say that you lose (part of) your rights via bad conduct. Not having the same complement of rights as other humans, it would become okay for you to be treated differently from other humans. This would allow us to jail people and even, in rare cases, to kill them. It would even justify partial -- and, in some cases, complete -- slavery.

But another solution is to say that rights are merely means and that the harmony of interests is the end. On this view, rights protect you from initiated force -- but not retaliatory force -- due to what it is that is required by the harmony of interests. Not offering protection against justice in the first place -- because that would contradict the harmony of interests which rights rest on -- the question of whether retaliatory force violates rights never arises.

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 10/16, 12:33pm)


Post 81

Sunday, October 16, 2011 - 6:45pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
P M H,

One problem that occurred in a previous debate on the same issue is that multiple "definitions" are given for rights, even by Rand.  The concept is difficult to describe in a single sentence.  The theory or principle of individual rights is not some first order concept we can point out in reality.  It is the product of a complete moral theory, with historic information, semantic concerns, etc.  Giving it a one sentence description is not going to provide all of the relevant details.  At best, it's used to identify some key aspect of it and differentiate it from other concepts in order to provide clarity.  In the previous debate, there were several quotes from Rand on the nature of rights.  In one, she described it as a condition of existence.  In another, she called it a moral principle.  And a moral concept.  Elsewhere, I believe she referred to it as a moral claim.  If you take any one of these descriptions as definitive, it will appear to contradict the others when in fact each description is merely describing some facts about it.

Similarly, saying that rights are "moral principles that describe human freedom in a social context" is true, but not complete. As a moral principle, it says more than that there is a such thing a human freedom in a social context.  Moral principles describe causal connections, which this 'definition' doesn't even mention.  As a moral concept, rights should describe morally appropriate behaviors, which this definition doesn't discuss or even hint at.  Taken in isolation, this is not a useful definition, and if you try to change the concept to be consistent with it, it empties the concept of all of it's important insights.

You suggested the alternative of taking this nearly useless view of rights as a given, or throwing away the definition.  A better alternative is to realize that a definition doesn't describe a concept in detail, but attempts to identify the concept and differentiate it from other concepts.  If someone gave this 'definition', we would know what they were talking about.  But we'd know because we're already familiar with the concept, and this definition allows us to understand which concept you are referring to.  But the definition doesn't fully describe the concept, nor the moral and philosophical foundations including the arguments that give rise to it.

On your response to Bill, I don't like the attempt to claim that we are "respecting his choice" by punishing the murderer.  His consent is not needed, and trying to argue that he is somehow "ultimately" consenting to punishment is so far a stretch that any actual violation of rights could be called consent.  Nor should we delude ourselves into thinking that he would accept being killed himself with joy and open arms.  And what happens if he changes his mind? 

No, we don't punish the murder to acquiesce to his will.  We don't expect or demand that he desires.  We use retaliatory force because it is in our interests, not his.  His desire to murder but not suffer consequences is not our concern.  Our own lives, and the harmony of interests that makes them possible, is our concern.

Ed, one thing to note is that while the harmony of interests is important, it does not excuse any use of force.  There are places where someone may be rude, which breaks down that harmony of interests, but we wouldn't be justified in using force.

Also, I think I see why Bill thinks your are complicating things.  You've previously stated that the murderer's rights remain unchanged.  While you claim to have a new position, you've avoided wording it to say that his rights are reduced/gone.  Mostly you've focused on the point that retaliatory force is appropriate, and doesn't violate rights.  But that is consistent with saying that his rights still exist 100%, but that retaliatory force magically doesn't violate them.  Even with your posts suggesting agreement, it isn't clear that you aren't still using strange definitions that attempt to achieve the same outcomes but aren't consistent with the 'normal' usage.


Post 82

Monday, October 17, 2011 - 6:52amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Joe,

Ed, one thing to note is that while the harmony of interests is important, it does not excuse any use of force.  There are places where someone may be rude, which breaks down that harmony of interests, but we wouldn't be justified in using force.

There are 2 senses of a harmony of interests:


1) whether folks have commensurate long term values (metaphysical)
2) whether folks are all getting along in the "right here and now" (circumstantial)

The second sense, to which your quote refers, is actually irrelevant. Whether folks are circumstantially rude doesn't affect the broader harmony of interest alluded to in the first sense. That broader harmony of interests comes from our nature, not from anyone's particular behavior.

You've previously stated that the murderer's rights remain unchanged.  While you claim to have a new position, you've avoided wording it to say that his rights are reduced/gone. 

But my position isn't brand new. I've argued it since about 2009. More than a couple of years ago, though, I had a different position. I thought -- like Mortimer Adler did -- that capital punishment (even if "deserved") might possibly be rights violation. However, what it is that is new is my ability to communicate the justification for my position -- by appeal to the harmony of interests.


Mostly you've focused on the point that retaliatory force is appropriate, and doesn't violate rights.  But that is consistent with saying that his rights still exist 100%, but that retaliatory force magically doesn't violate them.  Even with your posts suggesting agreement, it isn't clear that you aren't still using strange definitions that attempt to achieve the same outcomes but aren't consistent with the 'normal' usage.

When I say "inalienable" -- such as when referring to 'inalienable' rights -- then what I mean is that it is something that you "cannot lose by bad conduct." My definition of inalienable makes it similar to the word "immutable" (unchanging; permanent).


If you accidentally think of rights as supra-contextual absolutes (as floating abstractions, or even as axioms!), then you will also think that retaliatory force could possibly violate them. If, instead, you think of rights as the means to implement a social order that is in tune with (doesn't contradict) a harmony of interests, then speaking of rights as offering protection from retaliatory force, or "protection from justice", would be a category mistake (it would be dropping the context).

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 10/17, 1:06pm)


Sanction: 6, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 6, No Sanction: 0
Post 83

Tuesday, October 18, 2011 - 12:15amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed, you're not making it easy to understand your position.  Even here, you refuse to say in a straightforward way whether the murderer still has full rights or not.  Are you intentionally avoiding this?  I don't have the patience to try to sort your views out.

Instead I'll point out once again that if rights are completely unaffected by your actions, and therefore are completely unaffected by what other morally should or shouldn't do, the term stops having any moral significance. 

Imagine the murderer in jail. 

He says "I have a right to go wherever I please!". 

The warden says "That's absolutely true!  It is your right to leave here if you wish".

"Great", replies the murderer, "I'll just walk through that gate right now".

"No, we're going to prevent you from doing that.  The guards will shoot.  Sorry".

"But you said it is my right!  I have a right to leave!  You can't tell me I have the right to leave and then tell me you'll use force to stop me!"

The warden replies, "You do have a right to leave any time!  That's a metaphysical fact, unaffected by the fact that you killed all those people.  You have the right to freedom of action."

"But that doesn't make sense", says the murderer.  "Freedom of action means freedom from coercion!  I'm not free to leave if you're going to shoot me.  There is no freedom there.  In what sense do I have a right to leave if you also claim a right to stop me with lethal force?"

"That's simple", replies the warden.  "When I say you have a right, I mean that human nature, in order to live a fulfilling life in a harmony of interests with others, should be free to act on his own judgment.  You are a human being, and so you have this right along with everyone else.  The fact that you murdered people doesn't change that fact.  You have a right to freely choose your actions.  We do not have any moral obligation to refrain from shooting you."

"No, no, no", cries the murderer.  "Freedom means freedom from coercion from others.  If you're going to shoot me or beat me when I try to leave, I'm not free.  Saying that I have a right to something means that it is morally wrong for others to use violence to stop me.  If I do have such a right, then you would be violating that right by threatening or using violence against me!"

"Well, no", the warden explains.  While you have a right to leave anytime you want, our use of violence against you doesn't count as a violation of your right.  Your right is perfectly intact.  Retaliatory force doesn't count."

"Why not??!?!?!"

The warden answers, "Category mistake".

The murderer says "Then you are invalidating the idea of a right.  You are saying I have a right to do something, but that it is legitimate for people to use violence against me.  But normally saying someone has a right indicates that they should be free to do it, and anyone who prevents them is in the wrong.  You've flipped it entirely around.  You aren't really saying that I have a right to leave.  You're saying that under the right conditions I would have it.  But since I murdered people, I do not possess the right anymore."

Warden: "Of course you have a right!  You are a human being.  It's just that in this particular case, you will be shot if you exercise your right, and that it is morally appropriate for that to happen".

The murderer replies "You are claiming that a right is some kind of quality that exists because of the potential of human beings to live within a peaceful society.  This quality is unaffected by whether a person is actually living peacefully.  The potential matters, not the actual.  So when you say I have a right, you are simply saying that under different circumstance it would be appropriate for me to leave and expect not to be shot.  It's not a word that describes things as they are, but describe what might be possible.  It makes no judgment about the world as it is, and provides no moral opinion about whether a person should actually be free to act or not."

"Why would you say that?", asks the warden.

The murderer replies, "Simple.  If these "rights" are completely unaffected by right or wrong, by living peacefully or murdering others, by whether a person should be free to leave or forced to stay, then they don't really provide any moral content at all.  They've become meaningless.  You've destroyed a perfectly good word.  And for that, you will die!"

*strangles warden to death*
*guards pretend not to notice*


Post 84

Tuesday, October 18, 2011 - 1:34pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Joe,

Even here, you refuse to say in a straightforward way whether the murderer still has full rights or not.  Are you intentionally avoiding this?
I'm not refusing to say anything. I am and have been saying that a murderer still has full rights. Back in the first post of this thread, Bill quoted me as saying this:
Because the right to life doesn't originate with/from chosen actions, it also doesn't end with/from chosen actions.
Another way to say that is that murderers still have full rights.

Imagine the murderer in jail. ...
[followed by your illustrative analogy]

It's in the scope of rights where we disagree, Joe. For me, if you have a right to life it means a right not to be murdered. Murder is something that happens to innocent people. Sometimes, however, people are killed (e.g., animal attacks, war, capital punishment) and in retrospect, we can say that they were killed but not murdered. This is what allows me to say that capital punishment (i.e., the judicious killing of others) doesn't violate an intact right to life.

And more to your analogy, the scope of freedom isn't so large that we could call it license. That's the reason for the distinction between freedom and license. License means you get to get away with bad conduct, but freedom doesn't mean being able to get away with bad conduct. Having the right to freedom doesn't mean you have the license to leave your jail cell.

Ed


Post 85

Tuesday, October 18, 2011 - 2:29pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

You wrote, "Because the right to life doesn't originate with/from chosen actions, it also doesn't end with/from chosen actions."

Sometimes these 'symmetrical' statements have the sound of logic yet really don't hold up. For example I have property rights that originate with my nature as a human being - and that are universal, and not, as you say, with/from chosen actions. But that doesn't mean that my particular property right can't be sold, exchanged, discarded or whatever by my voluntary action. Any adult owns the blood within his veins. But he also has the right to sell it. Once sold, he no longer has the rights to that blood that was sold.

Rights are inalienable in the sense that it can not be alienated (separated from me) by others. I might be able to sell or give away the right to the use of a pint of blood, but no one has the right to take it from me by force. So, inalienable doesn't mean there are no circumstances where I can't abandon it voluntarily. The same with my Freedom of action. I can contract away a specific expression of my freedom - for example, a "Do not compete" clause in a contract when a business is sold. By your approach suicide would always be murder - self-murder, but none the less murder. Your view of rights keeps them from being attached to the individual in way that the individual could be said to own them. Given that, how could we ever say "I have the right to..." or, "it is my right to..."

Rights origonate from a metaphysical base that makes them universal to humans, but they attach to individuals and become the individual's rights. If I trade my right to open a store of a certain kind within 100 miles of the store I sold with a "Do not compete" clause in the sales contract, then I have a limited degree of freedom - it was done voluntarily. Just as the commission of crime is always voluntary (by definition). Commit a crime - give up some rights.

Rights come to from our nature and without a chosen action, but once we 'have' them and begin to take actions, some of those volitional actions can change our instantiation of rights - our 'copy' if you will. Everybody got the same copy at the time rights attach (birth) but once we have them in hand, and we are competent to make rational, volitional action, we can modify them.

In one sense this a form of intellectual modeling since they are not a physical/chemical entity that we will one day see under a powerful microscope. But in another sense it is a key aspect of our moral relationship to others and as an individual our relationship can change within this area. Murder would be a big change in this relationship. The most sensible way to model this new relationship is to see that we have given away some degree of rights that is proportionate to rights that the crime violated. We will make the laws that determine appropriate legal reactions to that murder based upon the degree and kind of rights our model says were discarded (becoming our limit to what can be done to a murderer - i.e., will be what we can RIGHTFULLY do him).

Post 86

Wednesday, October 19, 2011 - 2:28pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

For example I have property rights that originate with my nature as a human being - and that are universal, and not, as you say, with/from chosen actions. But that doesn't mean that my particular property right can't be sold, exchanged, discarded or whatever by my voluntary action.
Okay, but we have both got to be careful of equivocation here. Having property rights in general and having the right to some (specific) property are not the same thing, although they are related. Some things true of one, aren't true of the other.

By your approach suicide would always be murder - self-murder, but none the less murder. Your view of rights keeps them from being attached to the individual in way that the individual could be said to own them.
I see what you mean that, in order to own something, you have got to be able to sell it, or at least to give it away. If you can't sell something -- or give it away -- then you don't (can't) own it. I think this is an example of the equivocation I warned about above. Every specific, concrete thing we own can be sold, or given away.

I'll say more later, but have to go for now ...

Ed


Post 87

Thursday, October 20, 2011 - 3:19pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I'm going to attempt to outline the 2 competing views here and I may make a mistake. For that reason, what I am about to write is subject to editing by others (such as by Joe, Bill, or Steve).

Rights view # 1
****************
Rights have either unlimited scope, or at least a scope so large that they would -- if intact -- protect folks from even judicial punishment (i.e., from justice).

Rights can be lost by bad conduct.

When we punish criminals, it's okay because they lost some of their rights by committing a crime (they engaged in bad conduct).
****************

Here's how that works.

1) You start with full rights.
2) You commit a crime.
3) This causes you to lose some of your rights.
4) Therefore, we can jail you without violating your rights (which are now either smaller or fewer than before).

Rights view # 2
****************
Rights have a scope that is limited by rational morality and the harmony of interests that coincides with that morality.

They are always negative rights in a moral context, so you can perform behavior that puts you outside of their protection (by going outside the moral context). 

Rights cannot be lost by bad conduct.

When we punish criminals, it's okay because they are outside of the protection afforded by rights in a moral context.
****************

Here's how that works.

1) You start with full rights.
2) You commit a crime.
3) This causes you to lose protection from force (to be susceptible to retaliatory force), a protection which was normally afforded to you as an innocent person (a moral claim against initiated force on the innocent).
4) Therefore, we can jail you without violating your rights (which are not things, in the first place, which could protect anyone from justice).

Let me know if I failed to properly outline the 2 views.

Now, Steve, you said:

... I have property rights that originate with my nature as a human being - and that are universal, and not, as you say, with/from chosen actions. But that doesn't mean that my particular property right can't be sold, exchanged, discarded or whatever by my voluntary action.
Okay, but property rights are negative rights (rights against something; e.g., rights against another's interference by committing theft, for example), and when you sell rights to something you are selling a positive right (a right to something). When we sell property to someone, we do not sell then a negative right. This is because that is a right that they already had in the first place. Instead, we sell a positive right (to something).

By your approach suicide would always be murder - self-murder, but none the less murder.
Actually, view # 1 above is the approach that might lead one to say that suicide is murder, because the "victim" did not perform the bad conduct that is -- on view # 1 -- that is required for someone to lose the rights that would protect them. On view # 2 (my view), rights don't protect against certain actions in the first place -- and would not be violated by someone's rational choice of suicide.

Your view of rights keeps them from being attached to the individual in way that the individual could be said to own them.
But my view of rights -- moreso than view # 1 -- keeps rights firmly attached to the individual. On my view, even bad conduct can't separate you from your rights.

If I trade my right to open a store of a certain kind within 100 miles of the store I sold with a ...
This, though not obvious, is actually trading a right to something, rather than trading a right against something.

The most sensible way to model this new relationship is to see that we have given away some degree of rights that is proportionate to rights that the crime violated. We will make the laws that determine appropriate legal reactions to that murder based upon the degree and kind of rights our model says were discarded (becoming our limit to what can be done to a murderer - i.e., will be what we can RIGHTFULLY do him).
But I'd argue that a murderer has stepped outside of the scope of protection of rights normally afforded to innocent people in moral situations. Whatever we end up doing to him should be guided by what is in the interest of justice (and our harmony of interests) instead of being guided by the "remainder" of rights that he supposedly has. One problem with the "remainder" view -- the view that you lose the rights you violate, or at least you lose an "equivalent" amount of rights which you have violated -- is that it means you can rape a rapist, and that criminals can be at least partial slaves. What protects folks from being slaves in the first place is rights, and criminals -- on view # 1 -- have lost some/all of their rights.

My view protects criminals from being turned into slaves, because it is justice (not a "remainder of rights") which guides their punishment.

Ed


Post 88

Thursday, October 20, 2011 - 3:28pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed, thanks for clarifying your position by saying that a murderer still has full rights.  I realize that was your position when the thread started, but you claimed to have modified your views in the middle of the thread.  So now I believe your position is that rights never change, but never include a protection from retaliatory force.

So in my murderer/warden exchange, it seems you can take two possible views:

1.)  The murderer does have a right to leave whenever he wants, since he would have such a right if he hadn't murdered someone, but he can expect to be shot if he does.
2.)  The murderer doesn't have a right to leave, since he never had a right to not be punished for his crimes.

The first approach severs his freedoms from his rights, in that case by saying he has a right when he certainly isn't free to act on it.

The second approach is also problematic.  If he didn't murder someone (and so wasn't convicted of murder), he actually would be free to leave.  The fact that he is not free to leave suggests that his freedoms have been reduced because of his actions.  If he would have had the right to leave before he murdered someone, but doesn't have the right afterwards, in what way has his concrete rights not diminished?


Post 89

Thursday, October 20, 2011 - 4:20pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed, we crossed posts.  Here's a reply.  You said:
Rights have either unlimited scope, or at least a scope so large that they would -- if intact -- protect folks from even judicial punishment (i.e., from justice).
It seems there must be two very different meanings of rights in play here.  So what meanings are in use?

1.)  Rights describe the scope of a freedom.  From Rand : "A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man’s freedom of action in a social context."  Let's look at how this definition plays out in your two examples.

In the first view, we would say that when someone murders another, his freedom of action is reduced.  This is true.  Where he was free to move around or relocate, he is now confined to the prison.  His actual freedom of action has been reduced.

Note that given this meaning of rights, his normal freedom of action would protect him from being imprisoned, killed, etc. (all of the uses of retaliatory force).  If he was free to move around, it would be impossible to imprison him without violating that right.  Consequently in that view, his rights are reduced.

In the second view, saying that his freedom of action is never reduced by bad conduct doesn't make any sense.  Of course it's reduced.  Where he was free before, he is no longer free.

So that was the first meaning of rights.  What is the second meaning?  It's hard to tell. Perhaps you can provide it.

We know some things about it.  We know that rights don't refer to a person's freedom of action anymore.  They no longer say what he is free to do.  This is because of the claim that rights do not change with bad conduct.

You've said that a person doesn't have a right to avoid retaliatory force.  So we know that this meaning of rights somehow is limited only to morally expected freedoms.

We could try saying something like:

2a.) Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue

This would allow retaliatory force...but this looks like the first meaning.  More importantly,  the actual freedoms would still change on the act of murder.  We can't refer to the actual scope of freedom or to the concrete rights, since those actually change when someone murders.  We need something that is more abstract.

2b.)  Rights describes the system of morally sanctioned freedoms.

This approach doesn't refer to the actual freedoms, but instead focuses on the theory or justification behind it.  Everyone has the same "system" of rights, even though their actual morally sanctioned freedoms differ based on moral considerations of their past actions.

This one meets the criteria, but it rules out saying things like you have a right to free speech.  In this case, rights stop referring to your specific freedoms, and instead refer to the theoretical system as a whole.  It might be better named "rights theory".

2c.) Rights refers to the fact that you should be free to within your morally sanctioned freedom of action.

Note here that this doesn't say what is morally sanctioned freedom of action, but simply says that you should be free to act within it, whatever it is.  This meets the criteria of saying that rights don't change...you always have the right to act within the morally sanctioned freedom of action.  The scope of that freedom of action might change, but your right to act within it doesn't change.

The drawback to this approach is that it depends on forming a concept to actually describe the morally sanction freedom of action.  This is what "rights" usually describes, so there's likely to be confusion.

Ed, I'd like to hear your own definition that somehow meets your criteria and retains its usefulness as a concept.  Right now, I think your language is too vague for anyone to understand your position, or even for yourself to note if there are contradictions or problems.  Clarifying what you mean by rights would go a long way towards resolving these debates.


Post 90

Thursday, October 20, 2011 - 5:48pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

On your Rights View #1:

- Rights don't have "unlimited" scope, but rather they are limited only by not including anything that involves initiation of force, threat to intitiate force, fraud or theft. All things that don't violate choice are things a person has the right to do.

-Technically rights don't "protect" anyone in the sense of the rights being an active force. Rights, moral principles, define. People have to grasp the principle of creating laws that derive from these moral principles and then enforce them - and that will create the best environment for human behavior that is within the scope of rights and the best environment for discouraging behaviors that are not within the scope of rights. That environment is the "protection" of those living in that jurisdiction.

- When someone initiates force against another, they must step outside of the scope of rights. They still have their rights except for any right to not experience appropriate force that is either self-defense, or retaliation. They stepped outside of their sphere of rights to initiate force, and when in that area, they must be seen as without the right to resist or retaliate or defend for one simple reason: There could never be a right to violate a right.

- The murderer still has the right to his life or freedom in all contexts but one. That one context where he doesn't have the right to his life or freedom is defined by the scope of his violation of anothers rights. That scope says the murderer has the moral right to defend against some other prisoner who might attempt to kill him. That scope does not provide him with the moral right to resist reasonable retailiation.

- If instead of a murderer, we were talking about a petty thief, the scope would be different. The acts that the thief committed violated fewer rights than the murderer and therefore the amount of retaliation that would be moral is also less. The thief can be morally jailed but not for life, and can not be executed - not morally.

Justice, in this view, is matching the laws to properly reflect the moral principles - the individual rights, making them into objective laws, and applying them properly. It can be parsed to infinity ("Is it more moral to jail a particular petty thief for 30 days, or 31 days?") It is impossible to achieve perfection in this, or to even measure it beyond a crude way, but perfection isn't needed.
-----------------------

That is my understanding (or restating) of your view #1, but it is very close to your view #2 in some ways. I don't understand your "harmony of interests" or what specifically you mean by "rational morality" - I think rights have to have the scope set as "Everything that doesn't use initiation of force, threat to initiate force, or fraud or theft."

You do lose rights from bad conduct, but only the rights to resist appropriate self-defense or appropriate retaliation.

You said, "When we punish criminals, it's okay because they are outside of the protection afforded by rights in a moral context."

Yes, exactly.
-----------------

I disagree with what you said in point #4, "...[rights] which are not things, in the first place, which could protect anyone from justice..."

Justice is dependent, in this context, upon rights - they come first. We don't know what would be just without knowing what is a right. "Is it just to imprison a murderer? Yes, because we don't have the right to initiate force."

Post 91

Thursday, October 20, 2011 - 6:52pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

You wrote, "...property rights are negative rights (rights against something; e.g., rights against another's interference by committing theft, for example), and when you sell rights to something you are selling a positive right (a right to something). When we sell property to someone, we do not sell then a negative right. This is because that is a right that they already had in the first place. Instead, we sell a positive right (to something)."

Rights are the moral sanction for an action. It is valid to say that I have a right to breathe, to walk, to buy things, to sell things, etc. The distinction between positive and negative rights is a bit different. What is usually referred to as a positive right is the right to something others produce even if they don't want to provide it - like a 'right' to healthcare, to food, to shelter. The way you are discussing positive and negative rights would be that I have a positive right to speak my mind and a negative right to be free from government censorship, threats of force against me should I speak, etc. That's not the usual way positive rights are discussed.

I think "positive rights" is a concept that is useful except when it refers to having a right to products or services that are produced by others even if the producers don't want to provide them.
------------------

You said, "When we sell property to someone, we do not sell then a negative right."

The concept of "property" is a shorthand concept. It should be understood that "property" is a bundle of rights that connect a person to a thing and that each twig in that bundle of rights is a different action relative to that thing that can be taken with full moral right. For example, if you own a car, you have a bundle of rights relative to that car which would include the right to drive it, to lease it to another person, to let a friend drive it, to sell it, to repair it... etc. You can exchange one or more of those twigs to someone else. They are 'rights' that you own. I can give up (e.g., sell) the right to drive my car during a period of time, because I have leased it to someone who would not want me to be driving the car while he has it on lease.

We have formed the habit of referring to the car as the property. But it is the bundle of rights relative to that car that is really the property.
-------------------------

You wrote, "My view protects criminals from being turned into slaves, because it is justice (not a "remainder of rights") which guides their punishment."

Justice becomes a floating abstraction when not derived from rights. If you can't say what right a person has, then you can't say what is just or not just in an action.


Post 92

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 10:16amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Joe,

You asked for me to define rights and I would use the definition by Rand that you provided but with an emphasis on her limitation of a social context.

A social context is a "society" (geographically-distinct folks cooperating and interrelating). I believe that you cannot say that prisoners would also be "in society" -- in order to extend her context-limited definition to prisoners. Prisoners are not included in her definition because they are outside of the social context. It is even said to prisoners as they are released, that they are re-entering "society" (re-entering a social context).

You've said that a person doesn't have a right to avoid retaliatory force.  So we know that this meaning of rights somehow is limited only to morally expected freedoms.
This seems true. Morally expected freedoms are those freedoms that we expect in a social context, but that we do not also expect while serving time for our crimes in prison.

We could try saying something like:

2a.) Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue
But I'd change this back to:
Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue in a social context. Rand's definition is limited by context, but your "2a" is not.

2b.)  Rights describes the system of morally sanctioned freedoms.
I agree with you that, if anything, the above should be called "rights theory."

2c.) Rights refers to the fact that you should be free to within your morally sanctioned freedom of action.

I agree with you that this one is confusing, so I would go back to the modified 2a above:

Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue in a social context.
Ed


Post 93

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 10:52amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

I don't understand your "harmony of interests" or what specifically you mean by "rational morality" ...
In order to understand them, think of their opposites:

What would a dis-harmony of interests look like?

What would an irrational morality look like?

Taking the second one first, the context was whether suicide was murder. It is possible for it to be moral to commit suicide. On a rational morality, for instance, if someone had an intractable condition which was unbearably painful. Besides the question of whether it can be moral to commit suicide (that question was just answered), there is also the question of the means. On a rational morality, someone might take a lot of sleeping pills to commit suicide. On an irrational morality, someone might commit suicide by detonating a nuclear bomb.

A nuclear bomb, because it kills others, is not a rational choice as a means for suicide -- and would not be included in the morally-sanctioned actions of a rational morality. Rationality is about weighing evidence and options. Because there are methods available to achieve the specific value of death without violating the rights of others, using a nuclear bomb as a device for suicide would not be morally-sanctioned on a rational morality.

If you look into the jungle, you see a dis-harmony of interests. The food for one animal means the starvation (or death) for another. The animals live "at each other's throats" so to speak. They do not create ways to cooperate with one another in order to achieve common goals and to further their individual goals. To be clear, some animals (such as ants) cooperate with one another to achieve common goals -- but they do not create the ways. Instead, their behavior is pre-programmed by the genetic code. And -- most importantly -- the pre-programmed behavior of other animals is in discord, or disharmony, with the ants.

Justice is dependent, in this context, upon rights - they come first. We don't know what would be just without knowing what is a right.
Okay, but this still doesn't alter the fact that rights won't morally protect you from justice. Which is just a quick way of saying that they're tied together and do not contradict one another.

Ed


Post 94

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 11:16amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

I think that you are using Rand's "social context" in a different way than she would have agreed with. She meant that an individual was going to interact with others - even if it was just one person on an otherwise deserted isle. And, a prisoner, after all, is interacting with other prisoners, and with guards - so rights still apply. Yes, the prisoner is released back "in society" but that is into wider society - a different society from the one in prison. (Fred would gladly remind us that if we were paying attention to what he has been writing, it is "societies" - plural :-)

It only takes two people to make a social context.
--------------

You say that we don't have morally expected freedom from retaliatory force while in prison. I'd say that reasonable moral expectations don't change. For example, when in prison for a crime one did commit, there is still a reasonable moral expectation of an incarceration that is appropriate to the crime - for example, excluding torture. In other words, going from one society into a sub-society (one that lives under the same laws - same general geographical area) doesn't take away the general moral expectations.

Each rational individual understands BEFORE they commit a crime that they can be subject to retaliatory force. They don't have to wait till after they have committed the crime and are in prison to understand that they are being subjected to that retaliatory force. The understanding existed in the entire society - not just in the subset of that society that is prison.

Note that under your understanding a person who initiated violence that resulted in death, would still have his full set of rights and moral expectations UNTIL put in prison... in some wierd way, it becomes the putting in prison itself that modifies his rights or moral expectations. But if that is the case, how did authorities acquire the 'right' to imprison him? And if it is the act of imprisoning him that effects the change, then a wrongly accused man loses his rights/expectations when imprisoned! We can't get away from the understanding that if a man is imprisoned, say on a desert island, and kept there by authorities, rights are still in play because there is this interaction between the prisoner and the jailers - and that makes for issues of individual rights. Does he have the right to leave the island, or do they have the right to hold him their?
--------------

"Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue in a social context."

I believe that statement matches perfectly with Rand's understanding of rights, but I don't believe she was using "social context" in the way you are. You would end up with different sets of rights for different societies - for example, Australia back when the English used it as a large prison. And when it is a tyranny that imprisons good people, then your definition has the tyrannts as rightful, and the prisoners... not so much.

Rand wrote, “Rights” are a moral concept—the concept that provides a logical transition from the principles guiding an individual’s actions to the principles guiding his relationship with others.

So "rights", by her understanding, are the guides to our individual actions whenever other people are involved (be that in prison, or free - be that in a free society or a tyranny.
--------------

She went on to say that "rights" became the "...link between the moral code of a man and the legal code of a society, between ethics and politics. Individual rights are the means of subordinating society to moral law."

But notice that the laws, the politics, the subordination of society to moral law... all of these include prison. We have laws that prescribe treatment of prisoners, our politics doesn't end at the prison gate, and we force prisons to observe standards of moral treatment. So, what I'm saying is that prisons are within society in the sense that Rand used the term.

Post 95

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 11:57amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

I don't see that "harmony of interests" plays a part in defining or validating rights. It is true that we can see a greater harmony of interests under rights than under the 'laws' of jungle survival, but that isn't the same as using harmony of interests as a standard - for determining what is or is not a right.

The only natural harmony of interests that I can see at a fundamental level is that I cannot use force against another and that they cannot use force against me - that this moral status is recipricol and universal and could maximize everyone's capacity to survive and flourish. But the rights must be implemented into objective law and, in practical terms, that law must be widely understood and it must be effectively enforced, and that this progression of moral to legal to enforced creates a society where a harmony of interests exists as an environment - all that as opposed to stating it as a theoretical construct that arises from rights.

To me, harmony of interests is more like a description of one of the aspects of the society we could achieve with rights once they are translated into good law and understood and enforced... and not a defining characteristic of moral rights.
-----------------

You wrote, "...rights won't morally protect you from justice..."

I agree that rights and justice are tied together (they overlap) and I agree that they don't contradict each other. But I still find your phrasing off-putting.

Justice is a state that exists when rights are not violated. Justice is missing when a right is violated.

Rand speaks of Justice as ...the act of judging a man’s character and/or actions exclusively on the basis of all the factual evidence available, and of evaluating it by means of an objective moral criterion...

I believe that justice is the moral state that exists in a specific context when the good or bad consequences of an action or series of actions are a product of the character of the those whose acts brought about the consequences. If a man chose to steal something and the court finds the man guilty - that is justice. If he gets off because the jury felt sorry for him, that would not be justice. We make a moral judgment of the state that follows actions that were volitional and reflected moral choices to determine if it was just or unjust.

Rights don't protect - not directly. They state a moral principle which should be observed. There can be actions taken on the basis of rights that protect - like self-defense, or like a court sentencing a guilty murderer to jail. If justice is a moral state resulting from an action like self-defense or the murderer being imprisoned, then the rights were the basis for achieving justice. In a tyranny, the self-defense might be disallowed in which case rights wouldn't protect you from injustice. Or, a politically connected murderer might be turned loose, in which case rights wouldn't morally protect one from injustice.

But in no way that I can imagine does it make sense to say "rights won't morally protect you from justice."

Post 96

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 1:50pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

I think that you are using Rand's "social context" in a different way than she would have agreed with. She meant that an individual was going to interact with others - even if it was just one person on an otherwise deserted isle. And, a prisoner, after all, is interacting with other prisoners, and with guards - so rights still apply.
Our question is whether criminals are inside of or outside of a social context. You claim they are inside and I claim they are outside. I looked it up and the closest thing I found from Rand was a definition -- in the Lexicon -- of "Social System":

A social system is a code of laws which men observe in order to live together.

Now, I would claim that criminals are outside of the context of a "social system" because they aren't observing a code of laws in order to live together. Rand said that a social system is a code men observe so that they can live together -- and criminals don't do that. Now, we can haggle about whether a social system adequately represents a social context. I say that it does. It may simply be a discussionary impasse, but I would say Rand would agree with me that incarceration isn't a social context.


It only takes two people to make a social context.
Is that all it takes? Imagine this: If there were 2 people on an island and they both had thought they were alone and, as soon as one saw the other, he rushed up and killed him and ate him -- was that a social context? In other words, if the 2 men aren't living together, but living only as predator and prey -- can that really be called a social context? If a social context requires living together, then the answer seems to be: no.


You say that we don't have morally expected freedom from retaliatory force while in prison. I'd say that reasonable moral expectations don't change. For example, when in prison for a crime one did commit, there is still a reasonable moral expectation of an incarceration that is appropriate to the crime - for example, excluding torture.


I agree that there is a reasonable moral expectation of appropriateness (an expectation that the punishment fits the crime). I don't see how it is relevant, though.

Note that under your understanding a person who initiated violence that resulted in death, would still have his full set of rights and moral expectations UNTIL put in prison... in some wierd way, it becomes the putting in prison itself that modifies his rights or moral expectations.
This seems like it's from way out in left field, Steve. Either I didn't communicate myself well enough, or you didn't listen well enough. Could you please elaborate on how it is that what I said would lead to the obnoxious instance of man committing a murder (an initiation of violence resulting in death) and having rights and expectations and then, at the moment he passes into the front door of the prison, these rights and expectations magically vanish or change?


Because it is so far out there -- so unexpected and foreign to me -- I am going to wait for an answer to this question before continuing my response.

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 10/22, 1:55pm)


Post 97

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 3:19pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

In Post 84, you wrote, "For me, if you have a right to life it means a right not to be murdered."

That, I think, is your mistake. To be sure, a right to life includes a right not to be murdered, but that's not what it means. It means a right to self-sustaining, self-generated action. A murderer does not have that right; if he did, we could not justifiably deprive him of it.

Post 98

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 4:48pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

We still disagree. I said that it only takes two people to make a social context... and I think that is obvious. But you said, "Is that all it takes? [2 people] Imagine this: If there were 2 people on an island and they both had thought they were alone and, as soon as one saw the other, he rushed up and killed him and ate him -- was that a social context? In other words, if the 2 men aren't living together, but living only as predator and prey -- can that really be called a social context? If a social context requires living together, then the answer seems to be: no."

Did the cannibal and his victim constitute a social context? Inside our discussion here, yes. You, Rand and I all recognize that there must be more than one person - in some context - to even have rights as an issue. Well, that person that was killed and eaten had the right to not be killed. If he was totally alone on that island, that would not arise. The very instant that even just one other person is involved, the issue of rights exist.

A social context does NOT require living together. My rights can be violated by someone on the other side of the world that lives under a different government, and has never even been within thousands of miles of me. Like someone that launches a ballistic missle towards me. If there were no one else on earth, my rights couldn't be violated. This is why I say that "social context" means that rights are violated by other people - that is the social context in it's fundamental meaning. When the concept of rights is used to create laws, that is the use of social context to mean a geographic area to be covered by the laws. To understand "social" in the context we are discussing, think about potential interactions. In the context of individual rights it is a reference to the existence of two or more individuals and at least one of them has the capacity to act in a way that would violate another's rights.

There is an underclass of criminals, like auto-theft rings, and they are part of the overall society - of our social context - that we live within. They are predators and any one of us could become prey. That doesn't mean that rights don't exist (unless you are saying that a car thief loses some portion of his rights by the act of stealing a car - that I'd agree with). In principle, the car thieves and the rest of us are no different in principle than you example of the cannibal and his victim - both are in a social context.
----------------------------

You said that the prison is not part of the social context. Does that mean that their are no rights at all inside a prison? Are you claiming that it is okay to kill a person that is in prison for nothing more than writing a bad check?
----------------------------

A system is a mechanism that is constructed to serve a purpose. A social system created for the purpose of protecting rights would include things like laws, courts, and prisons. A social context is NOT the same thing as a social system.

You said, "Now, I would claim that criminals are outside of the context of a 'social system' because they aren't observing a code of laws in order to live together. "

Criminals are a part of the social system we have created to enforce moral principles via laws, police, courts and prisons - that system focuses on laws to define criminals, police to catch them, courts to convict them, and prisons to hold them. They are NOT outside of the social system. They may have acted outside of individual rights (by using force, fraud or theft). They act outside of the law when they violate a law. But they aren't outside of the social system. They aren't outside of the social context.
----------------------------

You wrote, "Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue in a social context."
And you wrote, "I believe that you cannot say that prisoners would also be "in society" ... Prisoners are not included in her definition because they are outside of the social context."

So those two things clearly go together to say that prisoners don't have rights. Yet before they were caught, they did exist in society. Therefore when I said that under your model, going into prison is what removes rights, I was just logically putting YOUR thoughts together.

So, hopefully, you now understand what I meant when I said, Note that under your understanding a person who initiated violence that resulted in death, would still have his full set of rights and moral expectations UNTIL put in prison... in some wierd way, it becomes the putting in prison itself that modifies his rights or moral expectations."

Post 99

Saturday, October 22, 2011 - 5:45pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill wrote, "...a right to life includes a right not to be murdered..." And he wrote, "A murderer does not have [the right to self-sustaining, self-generated action]..."

I agree with both statements completely, and I believe that the only way to understand them without contradiction is to say that when one violates the rights of another, they lose some rights of their own. First a person has a full set of rights, then they commit a murder, and then they don't have that full set of rights.

Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Forward one pageLast Page


User ID Password or create a free account.