| | Steve,
I said that it only takes two people to make a social context... and I think that is obvious.
Perhaps we will have to continue to disagree. You are using the word social in its broadest sense and I would claim that we need a narrower sense for this context. I would argue that the sense you are using is merely a synonym for plural as in "more than one life-form" -- and would apply equally to an ant colony or bee colony, to one animal killing another animal, to soldiers killing one another on a battlefield, and to murderers put to death in prison. In all those cases there is "more than one life-form."
Ants and bees are "social" animals because they live together. There is a plurality. But that is where the commonality between ants and humans stops. In that sense, you are arguing for use of the "ant colony" definition of social and I am arguing for use of the human definition of social.
There is an underclass of criminals, like auto-theft rings, and they are part of the overall society - of our social context - that we live within. They are predators and any one of us could become prey. That doesn't mean that rights don't exist (unless you are saying that a car thief loses some portion of his rights by the act of stealing a car - that I'd agree with). In principle, the car thieves and the rest of us are no different in principle than you example of the cannibal and his victim - both are in a social context.
You keep saying that there is a possibility that I might be thinking that rights are lost by bad conduct, but that is the opposite of my stated view. Please refer back to post 87, where I think I stated my view (I called it "view 2") most clearly.
The rights of these criminals afford moral protection against (initiated) force while they are observing a behavior code that allows them to live together with other human beings. If they break that code, however, their rights no longer protect them from (retaliatory) force. They have the same rights as before, but -- with regard to their punishment -- those rights become inapplicable to the new situation that they created. A murderer, for instance, could not appeal to his "right to life" in order to escape capital punishment. The right to life doesn't apply to such anti-social contexts. It has application in a social context where in order to have any force, you have got to have an initiation of force.
You can have force in prison without an initiation of force in prison, but that force is a retaliation of the initiated force that you instigated in the social context. Rights aren't rights against retaliatory force.
You said that the prison is not part of the social context. Does that mean that their are no rights at all inside a prison? Are you claiming that it is okay to kill a person that is in prison for nothing more than writing a bad check?
What I meant was that rights protect you from initiated force outside of prison, but not from the retaliatory force that you get while in prison. There is a potential equivocation here between a prisoner's sentence and their physical jail cell. The physical jail cell is a space made up of concrete and steel. And, inside of that space, people might initiate force on each other. The question is, if force is initiated inside of a jail cell, does it violate rights? The answer is: Yes, if it is not part of the judicial punishment of the criminal.
It's not that rights don't apply in jail cells, it's that rights don't apply in jail sentences/sentencing. There are full rights in prison, but the prisoner's sentencing puts him on a judicial path where his rights will not protect him from punishment.
A social system created for the purpose of protecting rights would include things like laws, courts, and prisons. A social context is NOT the same thing as a social system.
Under the premise of the "ant colony" (more than one life-form) definition of a social context, you are correct. I don't question how you arrived at that conclusion, I question the underlying premise. A social context, when applied to humans, would include a behavior code men observe in order to live together. With "social" animals (ants, bees, etc), the requisite behavior code is pre-programmed. With man, it has to be willfully observed.
You wrote, "Rights refers to the actions that you should be free to pursue in a social context." And you wrote, "I believe that you cannot say that prisoners would also be "in society" ... Prisoners are not included in her definition because they are outside of the social context."
So those two things clearly go together to say that prisoners don't have rights. Yet before they were caught, they did exist in society. Therefore when I said that under your model, going into prison is what removes rights, I was just logically putting YOUR thoughts together.
This is a tough point that needs more clarity. It is the same point made above about a prisoner's judicial sentence/sentencing and his physical jail cell.
There is the place (the prison) and there is the man (the prisoner). The man has placed himself outside of the context where rights afford him moral protection from force. We call it a prison but it is nothing special. It is just a place to put folks who have put themselves outside of the formerly-full protection of individual rights. They still have all of their rights, and their rights still morally protect them from initiated force (e.g., getting killed by prison guards for writing a bad check), but they don't have the same protection from force as they did in the social context they were in before they committed a crime.
Rights refer to the actions you should be free to pursue in a social context, not to actions you should be free to pursue in any/every context.
Ed
|
|