About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


Sanction: 20, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 20, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 20, No Sanction: 0
Post 80

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 8:37amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

Joe,

 

To avoid a lot of friction, I will try to keep my comments to facts, your own words and Barbara’s own words. I am specifically addressing your Post 74 and I will address the ideas in the order you presented them.

 

You started by expressing confusion about why some people on this thread considered Barbara’s article brilliant. I would like to point out that those who found this article brilliant are not just on this thread. There were many deeply knowledgeable Objectivists who attended the lecture who also found it brilliant. If you did not, that is your right. If you are truly puzzled, I believe it would be a good idea to ask some of the knowledgeable Objectivists – at least the ones you respect. I am sure several of them could clear up your puzzlement much better than I could.

 

You wrote that “the first two sections were about evil ideas or the immediacy of consequences.” This is where you skipped over a very important part of Barbara’s article. The first part actually gives the theme and expands on it. To quote Barbara, she stated right near the beginning.

 

“And that is what I want to discuss today: the immensely presumptuous moralizing, the wildly unjust condemnations, and the towering anger and outrage exhibited by so many Objectivists. I want to explain, as best I can identify it, why this happens—that is, what are the mistaken philosophical ideas that lead to it, and what appears to be the psychology of many of its practitioners.”

 Please note that she is not talking about all moral condemnation and rage, just the wildly unjust ones that she has seen by “so many Objectivists.” Note that this does not mean “all Objectivists” either. This will be important to remember as I go through the ideas.

 

The first two sections (more precisely, the second and third sections) were not about “evil ideas or the immediacy of consequences” as isolated topics. They were about two of the causes for the prominent moralizing by “so many Objectivists” that was her theme. She also did not stipulate that all unjust moralizers exhibited the same degree of each cause, or even that all unjust moralizers were moralizers because of the same causes. She merely gave an overview of the main reasons in general as she has observed them over a lifetime.

 

You mentioned the part about evil ideas, but did not discuss it. From the tenor of what you wrote, you did not consider this part important. Yet this is a strong philosophical component in exaggerated inflamed moralizing. (Remember, Barbara said she was going to discuss the philosophical reasons first, then the psychological reasons – so this is the philosophical part).

 

The subject of whether ideas are evil is actually at the base of the Kelley-Peikoff schism. (Kelley did some magnificent writing about it, too.)

 

Barbara’s point is that people are judged to be evil by the raging moralizers because the ideas these people believe are judged to be evil. But as Kelley correctly observes, an idea can only be correct or incorrect. Evil is attributed only to actions, i.e., consequences or intentions (both being actions, one physical and the other mental). Barbara also correctly mentions that only people can be moral agents, while ideas and emotions cannot be moral agents.

 

One of the main reasons that excessive moralizers use the philosophical component of accepting the notion that there are “evil ideas” is that this creates a short-cut to moralizing – it creates oversimplification. After noticing that “evil ideas” usually means “mistaken ideas” that contradict ours, she says:

 

It makes moral judgment so very easy, does it not? All we require in order to know that someone is worthless is to know that he holds convictions contrary to our own.

 

And if we hold such a view, we necessarily will morally denigrate and verbally abuse those who do not agree with us. We will be indignant at our opponents’ presumption in asking that we even consider or attempt to disprove their evil ideas. Instead, to the cheers of those who agree with us, we will ringingly denounce their dishonesty, their irrationality, their evasion, so that the world will recognize them for what they are.

 

And what superior and virtuous beings we are! And how incredibly smug and self-congratulatory! We cavalierly dispense with most of the human race for not agreeing with our philosophy.

 

In reality, a person is much more than his professed beliefs. He has a personal history and he has normal manners of acting and interacting with others. He has a temperament. He has many elements that constitute knowledge of him as a person in addition to his professed ideas. Yet the “evil idea” approach allows a flaming moralizer to blank out this additional knowledge and condemn the person as evil to the moralizer’s heart’s content.

 

So I disagree with you about the importance of this section. I find it to be a critical component in understanding the causes of the chronic overkill in moralizing.

 

The third section (your second section) is not exactly “immediacy of consequences” (the title was “Consequences as self-evident” to be precise). Barbara specifically mentioned a direct envisioning of the results of an idea – as if on a perceptual level – that prompted immediate anger. In this case, she was not talking only about moralizing rage. She was talking about a psychological trigger that causes anger based on a philosophical manner of integrating an idea.

 

She gave an example from her own life with respect to the draft. In her mind’s eye, she saw the vivid image of “a field strewn with the butchered bodies of dead and dying young soldiers, soldiers who were scarcely more than boys, who had been sent to bleed and die for purposes that were not their own.” In the case of Ayn Rand, she mentioned a letter to Nathaniel Branden not too long after Rand met him. Rand asked if the image of Hank Rearden came to mind when Nathaniel heard the term “selfish exploitation” and this caused him to blow up. In both cases, Barbara mentioned the visual image as a trigger for anger.

 

Then she mentioned that this, “at least in one respect,” was why Ayn Rand displayed a “quickness to pass negative moral judgments.” Let me emphasize for clarity, Barbara advanced this as one of the reasons, not as the only reason for Rand’s snap moral condemnations.

 

You wrote:

 

The point for both sections seems to be just because it's obvious to us, doesn't mean it's obvious to someone else.

 

 This is not precise, since it was not covered in the second section (your first section) dealing with evil ideas. In the following section, this was mentioned, but it was not the point. If you need a point for both sections, that would be oversimplification. Barbara was very clear that the doctrine of “evil ideas” leads to oversimplification in judging a person to be evil. And she was also clear that envisioning the consequences of an idea with a perceptual image leads to an oversimplification that blurs the understanding of the conceptual meaning of that idea. In both cases, oversimplification results in anger. If practiced consistently, the result is angry moralizing.

 

That is the point of those sections.

 

The idea that what is obvious to one is not obvious to another was mentioned almost in passing, as a further idea to her point. Barbara only devoted one paragraph to it, at the end of the section dealing with self-evident consequences:

 

It is true that many of our convictions may begin to seem almost self-evident to us. But we must recognize that this is not so, that we have learned the truth of them as a result of many complex and extended processes of observation and thought—which means that they are not self-evident to our opponents. Our opponents rarely disagree with us out of sheer perversity, willfully denying the evidence of their senses. We ought to treat them accordingly, to remember that we did not always know what is so clear to us today, and, very importantly, to remember the steps by which we came to know it.

 

You then wrote: 

I don't think those examples are representative of any significant number of people.

 For the case of the “evil ideas” doctrine, my own experience is completely at odds with yours because I see it all around me and in a large number of Objectivists, at least online. As one easy example, look at how religious people are consistently baited on Objectivist Internet forums and treated with harsh derision, regardless of whether they make a rational point about any other matter. There are other examples that are easily seen, but I don’t need to list them all. The idea is clear.

 

For the case of envisioning the consequences of an idea, I agree with you. I do not know many people who do that consistently – who immediately see perceptual images as the result of ideas in themselves, especially new ideas. Only very penetrating intellects seem to do that as a habit. Ayn Rand did. Barbara did. Nathaniel Branden did. Those are Barbara’s examples.

 

The impression I get from the flaming moralizers is that when they envision something, they see either a passage of Rand’s impassioned words or some kind of image of “trouncing an evil enemy.” They seem to want to relive the glory of Rand’s achievements in a ballsy manner. This is secondary to what Barbara mentioned, but it is true from my own observations. Of course, in this paragraph I am discussing my impressions of some very inflamed Objectivist people I have interacted with. Your own experience might have been different.

 

On evasion, you give a pretty good example of how exasperating it gets to discuss an idea with someone who doesn’t care. You ask if that is a justification for moral outrage, insinuating that this is evasion in all cases. But I would say that in some cases yes, in other cases no. The magic word, context, comes to mind in making that call. For example, a person might be open to an idea that challenges long-held beliefs, but he is not open at the particular moment you are talking to him because he is busy with something else. There are many contexts that could apply.

 

Still, I feel your pain from having experienced it myself. Yes, I do feel anger when I get brushed off. We all do. Whether I will call that person evil in an inflamed manner or not will depend on a lot of other information about both him and the situation.

 

But this is beside the point. It bears repeating that Barbara was not talking against anger per se. She was talking against unjust inflamed moralizing. So when you mention her correct observation that one cannot know the contents of the mind of another, and then ask:

 

But is she really arguing about very difficult and slight cases of evasion?  Is this where moral outrage comes from?

 

 you make the mistake I mentioned in my earlier post. She is not discussing where moral outrage in general comes from. She is discussing where unjust, i.e., not fully integrated, moral outrage comes from. She even used the term “irrational moralizing” at the start of this section on evasion. Once again, the concept of oversimplification is evident. It is easy to dismiss a person by saying he is evading. Her point is that much information is needed to make that call with certainty and the angry moralizers do not consider all the information needed. They oversimplify.

 

Thus your following conclusion does not accurately deal with her text. You treat her argument as if she were talking about all moral condemnation. She wasn’t.

 

She's almost entirely ruled out moral outrage with an almost-skepticism.  We can still judge the likes of Hitler, but pretty much all of our day to day judgments have to be thrown out because psychology hasn't progressed as a science enough.

 

But don’t take my word for it. Here are Barbara’s words on proper moral condemnation:

 

Of course there are thoroughly dishonest people in this world. Of course there are people who deserve the strongest possible moral condemnation. Of course there are people who push away guilt feelings and continue to act destructively and irrationally. Of course there are people who act without thinking, who mouth ideas they do not take the trouble to understand, who refuse to examine their own motives and purposes. Of course there are people who would rather die than think—and often do.

 

This partial paragraph occurs at the end of the section on evasion. For as much as I try to force my thinking, I just don’t see how this can be construed to apply only to “the likes of Hitler.”

 

In your examination of the section of the psychological causes of Objectivist rage, you already have switched gears and brand her arguments as if she were talking about rage in general by Objectivists. Here are your own words: 

The last section on psychological causes of rage was also lacking. 

 and  

Those are convenient ways to slander moral outrage…

 Barbara defined her terms at the very beginning of the article, the part you skipped. She was discussing “Objectivist Rage.” Here are her words from the start.

 

But what I call “Objectivist Rage” has a peculiar twist to it, unlikely to be found anywhere else except, paradoxically, in religion. It is almost always morally tinged. Those who question our ideas and those who oppose them, we are told, are not merely unintelligent, ignorant, uninformed; they are evil, they are moral monsters to be cast out and forever damned.

 

And that is what I want to discuss today: the immensely presumptuous moralizing, the wildly unjust condemnations, and the towering anger and outrage exhibited by so many Objectivists. I want to explain, as best I can identify it, why this happens—that is, what are the mistaken philosophical ideas that lead to it, and what appears to be the psychology of many of its practitioners.

 Barbara was discussing the psychological reasons for that. She was not discussing the psychological reasons for moral condemnation in general. Since your discussion of this section is based on a mistaken notion of her meaning, I see no point to debating the details, neither the charge of slander. But, when you ask: 

Did I skip over the really important part?

 As I stated earlier, I have to answer, “Yes you did.” You skipped over the beginning, where she defined what she was talking about. I respectfully suggest a closer reading of her article.

 

I could go on to your following posts with this same thoroughness, but this is getting way too long.

 

Michael

 


Post 81

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 10:04amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Michael,

I have so far stopped at this point in your post:

Barbara’s point is that people are judged to be evil by the raging moralizers because the ideas these people believe are judged to be evil. But as Kelley correctly observes, an idea can only be correct or incorrect. Evil is attributed only to actions, i.e., consequences or intentions (both being actions, one physical and the other mental). Barbara also correctly mentions that only people can be moral agents, while ideas and emotions cannot be moral agents.

If a person holds a conviction or idea other than your own that is incorrect, in other words, that if acted upon would be evil and they argue in support of this idea are they supporting evil?

 

What if you debate with them and show them the fallacies in their view and they continue to espouse this incorrect idea, is that evil?

 

 


Post 82

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 10:08amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Continuing on:

In reality, a person is much more than his professed beliefs. He has a personal history and he has normal manners of acting and interacting with others. He has a temperament.

What about a hypothetical person (I''m sure there were many people who fit this hypothetical) who supported the issue of slavery prior to the civil war. Let's say they didn't own any slaves and they were a fine and dandy person, but they argued that slavery was fine and supported it through voting or whatnot. Is that evil?

Ethan

(Edited by Ethan Dawe on 8/08, 10:10am)


Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Post 83

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 12:05pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ethan -- While your question is to Michael I'll add one point. Each of us must judge in the case of any particular person with respect to any particular issue if they are holding a mistaken beliefs that will have evil consequences because they're honestly mistaken, confused, intellectually lazy, acting in an evil way or perhaps a little of all of these.A professor in an American university who supports communism today, after the fall of the Soviet Union and all of the scholarly work showing the moral and economically evil consequences of communism, probably is evading at minimum or far worse. But you need to deal with the person -- read their material, talk with them -- to find this out. You can of course state in no uncertain terms that the ideas they are advocating are evil.

Concerning slave owners, let's look at George Washington. He grew up in a slave society and accepted the institutions around him. For the most part he was an individual of outstanding moral character and actions. But as he got older he came to see the problems -- and evils -- of slavery. At his death he freed his slaves. He also made provisions for their upkeep or training in a trade in the case of those young enough. I've seen his handwritten instructions -- under glass, of course -- at his home in Mount Vernon. Here's my op-ed on Washington.

http://www.objectivistcenter.org/cth--810-Example_Our_First_President.aspx


Post 84

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 12:11pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hi Ed,

I appreciate your response. How we deal with people is very important.

In my first example I noted the a debate was attempted and failed. Now, I know of cases like this where a person has had their errors, "incorrect ideas," or assertions explained to them and they have evaded and continued to espouse their incorrect ideas. I'm interested in Michael's response to this.

Ethan


Sanction: 11, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 11, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 11, No Sanction: 0
Post 85

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 12:57pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Is there a particular type of rage that is peculiar to Objectivism? I don't think so. Branden obviously holds this opinion and bases her speech on this premise.

One question occured to me while reading the speech, and that was, how are we then to distinguish between appropriate rage and innappropriate rage, given Ms Brandens assertion that it is difficult to know the roots (philosophical or psychological) of the response to certain ideas?

I suppose I stand alone in my belief that some ideas *are* evil. I might be presumptuous, but I do assume that there is a thin enough line between holding an evil idea (e.g. sex with children is ok), and the acting upon that idea, to raise my defenses and my rage.

Is the idea (above) simply incorrect? Is my anger if vented upon the person espousing the idea innapropriate and "irrational"?

The speech was technically well written, and the delivery may have been spot on. The argument was flawed however, and I would *not* categorise it as brilliant. One could easily substitute any ism in the title, and make the same claims that Mr Branden makes. Capitalism and Rage, Christianity and Rage, etc etc.


John

Sanction: 2, No Sanction: 0
Post 86

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 1:15pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
John wrote:

I suppose I stand alone in my belief that some ideas *are* evil. I might be presumptuous, but I do assume that there is a thin enough line between holding an evil idea (e.g. sex with children is ok), and the acting upon that idea, to raise my defenses and my rage.

You are not alone, John.  I will stand with you.


Post 87

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 1:29pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
MSK wrote (post 80):

But as Kelley correctly observes, an idea can only be correct or incorrect. Evil is attributed only to actions, i.e., consequences or intentions (both being actions, one physical and the other mental).
Kelley's critics have claimed this, too. Indeed, this is how 'Kelley severs fact and value' according to Peikoff in Fact and Value. However, it is false. He wrote the following in both Truth and Toleration and Contested Legacy of Ayn Rand (Chapter 3): "Because the effects of Marxist ideas are bad, moreover, we evaluate the ideas as bad."

B. Branden said:

An idea, like an emotional reaction, is not a moral agent. Only men and woman are moral agents; only they can be good or evil.
Of course, ideas don't act and agents do, but the latter disagrees with Kelley.

P.S. I do agree that some Objectivists are overzealous moralizers of other Objectivists.

(Edited by Merlin Jetton on 8/08, 2:38pm)


Post 88

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 1:29pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Sharon,

I also believe that there are essentially three groups of people in the manner of the bully, the bullied, and the bystander. Doug Casey wrote about something similar that scientists had observed with rats. It was in his book Crisis Investing for the Rest of the 90's.

The scientists observed the rats--alpha, beta, and gamma. Alpha rats were bullies. Beta were the bullied. Gammas were the "go along, get along" types. They also did quite well for themselves.

Politically, you could divide up the world into these groups:

1. People who want to tell everyone else what to do
2. People who want to be told what to do
3. People who want to run their own lives and think for themselves

I've long believed that if the third group separated themselves from the other two that the first two groups would probably wipe each other out.

Chris


Sanction: 10, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 10, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 10, No Sanction: 0
Post 89

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 2:56pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
John you write: Is there a particular type of rage that is peculiar to Objectivism? I don't think so. Branden obviously holds this opinion and bases her speech on this premise.

John, is there a particular type of rage that is peculiar to mafia?
or, is there a particular type of rage that is peculiar to terrorism? or, is there a particular type of rage peculiar to the savages, or, to religion, etc...etc...
My answer is yes to these questions. I just don't understand why  you think that this doesn't apply to objectivism.

(Edited by Ciro D'Agostino on 8/08, 3:00pm)


Post 90

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 4:39pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Luke:You are not alone, John.  I will stand with you.

We all know that , Luke! One thing that
puzzles me is your pleasure to say it at every chance you have.


Post 91

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 5:18pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I suppose I stand alone in my belief that some ideas *are* evil. I might be presumptuous, but I do assume that there is a thin enough line between holding an evil idea (e.g. sex with children is ok), and the acting upon that idea, to raise my defenses and my rage.

Is the idea (above) simply incorrect? Is my anger if vented upon the person espousing the idea innapropriate and "irrational"?








 John,
Ayn Rand considered homosexuality disgusting , would she affirm the same thing today?

Was Ayn Rand’s idea about homosexuality simple incorrect? was her anger and negative comments about homosexuality inapropriate and irrational?
CD



(Edited by Ciro D'Agostino on 8/08, 6:10pm)


Sanction: 2, No Sanction: 0
Post 92

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 8:40pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
MSK, you really need to work on trying to be more succinct.

I asked what was brilliant about her speech. In response, you've said that I overly generalized her statements, and she's only arguing against unjust moralizing. Even if I accepted that (which I don't), where's the brilliance again?

After reading your post, and resisting the urge to just debate all of your arguments, I'm still left not having a clue about what you thought was brilliant about it. Some of the points you seem to think were really good, like how a person is more then their professed beliefs, she either didn't make or only tangentially touched upon. I found this post by Hong far more illuminating:

http://rebirthofreason.com/Forum/ArticleDiscussions/0769_2.shtml#59

Most of your arguments seem to be that Barbara wasn't actually trying to argue against moral outrage in general, just faulty versions of it. Even if it were true, it doesn't answer the question about what is brilliant about it.




Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 5, No Sanction: 0
Post 93

Tuesday, August 8, 2006 - 9:20pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Joe,

In all due respect you just asked me:
I asked what was brilliant about her speech.
That was not your original question. You had originally asked:
Did I skip over the really important part?
Your words, not mine. I consider definition of terms to be the "really important part" of any article that should never be skipped over. You did skip over this and even asked about it.

So I answered.

The short answer did not satisfy you, so I decided to be thorough, especially as this error led to a series of mischaracterizations of Barbara's ideas. The point was to show the correct version of the ideas in Barbara's article in the face of misunderstanding prompted by skipping the definitions.

As to what I consider brilliant in Barbara's article, due to our difficulties in communication, I prefer to stay with my earlier suggestion:

You started by expressing confusion about why some people on this thread considered Barbara’s article brilliant. I would like to point out that those who found this article brilliant are not just on this thread. There were many deeply knowledgeable Objectivists who attended the lecture who also found it brilliant. If you did not, that is your right. If you are truly puzzled, I believe it would be a good idea to ask some of the knowledgeable Objectivists – at least the ones you respect. I am sure several of them could clear up your puzzlement much better than I could.

Still, here is a short answer. Barbara's article was brilliant for the same reason many articles are brilliant: she identified not-so-obvious causes and solutions to very obvious problems.

As I also stated, it is your right to find it not brilliant. Many knowledgeable Objectivists apparently do not share your evaluation. You have my answer here, which may not satisfy you, so I suggest you ask them if you are still puzzled.

(Note to Ethan: We can discuss The Contested Legacy of Ayn Rand by David Kelley in another place, since it deals with your questions about the moral./factual nature of ideas. A discussion of hypothetical situations on a tangent here has the potential to sidetrack the main issue.)

Michael


Post 94

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 12:11amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Luke wrote:

 John wrote:

I suppose I stand alone in my belief that some ideas *are* evil. I might be presumptuous, but I do assume that there is a thin enough line between holding an evil idea (e.g. sex with children is ok), and the acting upon that idea, to raise my defenses and my rage.

You are not alone, John.  I will stand with you.
I agree that some ideas are evil, if we're going by Rand's definition of evil: that which threatens the life of an organism.  The range of that evil is limited, however.  I thought of rephrasing her question about value: evil for whom and in what respect?  In other words, whose life is negated/threatened by the existence of an evil idea in someone's mind?  I think that it's the life of the person who carries the idea, first and foremost.

For example:

If faith short-circuits the rational mind, and the rational mind is necessary for flourishing as a human being, then an idea that (due to its nature) requires faith is evil, for the person who holds the idea.  However, that idea is not necessarily an immediate evil to my life, as I am not harmed by it (unless the idea is put into some sort of action that harms me).

Hmm.  I get the feeling that I should re-read the article and comments--I hope I'm not repeating something that's been said already.


Post 95

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 3:06amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hi Chris

I'll meet you in the Salon des Refusees  :?)

Sharon

Post 96

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 4:19amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Sharon,

What does that mean?

Chris


Post 97

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 4:23amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ciro wrote:

We all know that, Luke! One thing that puzzles me is your pleasure to say it at every chance you have.

One thing that puzzles me is why you say this in response to the very first post I made in this thread after over 80 posts preceded it.  However, I have noticed that I cannot understand most of your posts, Ciro, so this does not surprise me.


Sanction: 38, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 38, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 38, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 38, No Sanction: 0
Post 98

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 7:21amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Hello Ciro, re your post #89. My point was that inapropriate rage is not peculiar or prevalent in Objectivism, any more than it is elsewhere. The speech seems to suggest that it is.

Back to the speech:

"But what I call “Objectivist Rage” has a peculiar twist to it, unlikely to be found anywhere else except, paradoxically, in religion. It is almost always morally tinged. Those who question our ideas and those who oppose them, we are told, are not merely unintelligent, ignorant, uninformed; they are evil, they are moral monsters to be cast out and forever damned"

This quote from the speech is a pretty strong, and I think incorrect characterization, but for one point, that being the fact that when Objectivists rage it is morally tinged. Well of course it is! Love speaks to values and what is moral, so does admiration, and so does rage speak to what we find immoral. But Branden suggests that when Objectivists feel/express rage that it is irrational because those who question our ideas are "moral monsters". This overgeneralization is not the stuff of "brilliance". She is setting up a caricature of Objectivism without evidence.

She writes "we are told...". By whom, I would ask? With the exception of a very very few zealots I have never encountered anyone telling me this.

"And that is what I want to discuss today: the immensely presumptuous moralizing, the wildly unjust condemnations, and the towering anger and outrage exhibited by so many Objectivists."

Who are these many Objectivists? Does she (Branden) not realize that her entire speech is in fact, an "immensely presumptuous moralizing" talk rife with "wildly unjust condemnations"?

Ms Branden goes on to have us imagine a twelve year old Arab boy thusly:

"If this young boy considers himself a fundamentalist and upholds its doctrines, is he evil?" I guess him being twelve means that he should be cuddled instead of shunned? My own view is yes, if he upholds the doctines of the Koran he is upholding evil ideas. Furthermore, in todays context, he could easily threaten my survival and the survival of my family. She can't be serious here. Does she not know of the level of committment many of these children have to self-sacrifice and the destruction of others? Do I think his ideas are evil? Most definitely, inasmuch as they call for my destruction.

Ms Branden wishes to censure/educate/inform/control her audience in the following way:

"I wish only to deprive you of specifically moral outrage when it is unjustly directed at your opponents." She is not speaking to a child. I am fully capable of deciding when and when not to exercise my moral outrage. And if it is unjust, I do my best at self correction. But do I need Ms Branden to tell me this? And is it, again, the stuff of brilliance?

"But recognize, recognize clearly, that it is likely that many of your opponents do not grasp those consequences—and that, if they did, they would change their convictions." I will use the Arab boy as an example not because I wish to use an extreme, but because she herself used him. How likely is it that he will change his fundamentalist position?

I was amused at her anecdote of the young woman who experienced significant damage socially and emotionally at the hands of some dastardly Objectivists. She tells us the woman referrs to herself as a recovering Objectivist. This actually had me laughing. Is this an 8 yr old? No, she turned 21 recently. Yet apparently she has been traumatized and needs therapy or rehab? Much in the same way a bully is a bully even before Objectivism, I suspect the girl was an emotional basketcase before being so brutally "damaged".

Of course, The Atlas Society is a "significant exception". I wonder which other prominent Objectivist organization is *not* the exception, but the rule as far as this kind of rage is concerned? Have to give that some thought *wink*.

I find it puzzling that on one hand Ms Branden chides us with the fact that we cannot look into anothers mind, then proceeds to attempt to look into our minds with an analysis of what makes much of our rage irrational and unjust. This contradiction on her part is just one area in which the speech failed in my opinion. I enjoyed her book Principles of Efficient Thinking. Her speech however does not stand up to the very standards she set for herself.


John



Post 99

Wednesday, August 9, 2006 - 7:42amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I have noticed that I cannot understand most of your posts, Ciro,
Don't worry, Luke, It will not happen again.


Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Page 7Page 8Page 9Forward one pageLast Page


User ID Password or create a free account.