| | Next Level,
Think it out a little bit more. If the child notices that the blocks are of different colors, are you really claiming with certainty that he doesn't have the concept, "red" or that he hasn't associated the word, "red", with the concept? If the issue you're raising here is vocabulary, then the child must have some word associated with the concept that most people designate by the symbol "red." In that case, the child does understand the concept, but doesn't refer to the concept using the same symbol as everyone else. Obviously if the child instead though that the concept we denote "red" was called "green" instead, the Kindergarten teacher would correct the child, and he'd be on his merry way. However, so long as the child has the concept (and some word associated with a concept) the child can learn the proper words for things.
Of course, just because the child grows up in America and learns a certain collection of words to symbolize his concepts, that doesn't mean that it's the only way possible-- there are of course many languages. But my point is this-- we can "decipher" and learn other peoples languages, since we know that their words and our words correspond to the same concepts.
This, however, wasn't my point. If a child can't tell the difference between a red and a blue block, or thinks that the red blocks before him are the sole meaning of "red", then that child does not understand the concept of "red," and can't (and wouldn't) associate a word to try to describe it.
No, it doesn't depend on what I am talking about. If I granted you your claim that people learn things the way you say that they do, what words would show that a person understands topology in mathematics? For any mathematical system, they would have to present the definitions, and be sure that they understand the meanings of the concept presented in the definitions. There are no concrete "topological spaces" to point to in perceptual terms in order to say to a student "I mean this." With such an abstract idea, you need to give a definition to convey what you are talking about.
Most of the referents of mathematics are mental constructs and operations, but even in that case, understanding is not strictly about the words. I agree-- that's the way "Education" theorists today seem to think that children learn today: by memorizing words. One must know the meanings of the concepts that the words symbolize. But unless you have yourself researched and discovered all of mathematics on your own (which would be an amazing, impossible feat), you were taught mathematics, and the way that people are taught mathematics is with definitions involving concepts.
Words and many other symbols, including certain actions, when structured in the right way, communicate ideas. It is true that a person who understands topology would be highly unlikely to lack the ability to communicate it in some form. However, testing understanding is not a matter of words or symbols, but about the systematic inferences you draw from a person's use of those words or symbols. And it is possible to make the wrong systematic inferences (wrong in the sense that they do not capture the ideas that a person intends to communicate), though we often make reasonable or correct ones. Systematic Inferences? Do you mean guessing at what a person means? It shouldn't be necessary so long as the definition you present is correct. Presumably, a person in the position to learn what a topological space is knows what the genus (collections of subsets of a set) and differentia (which are closed under unions and finite intersections) mean. Given this definition, the next thing that you do is give the student a lot of examples of topological spaces to firm the idea, i.e., give the concept referents (what's known in the business as "motivating the definition"). This does not mean that the definition comes before the referents, since the student is already familiar with the examples.
The ideal of knowledge as "true, justified belief." The practical standards of truth and justification cannot be set in advance of knowing the context. Sometimes, the standard is a high correlation between cause and effect. Sometimes, it involves local proximity of causes. Sometimes, it is the view of the most advanced experts. Sometimes, it is whatever is enough to make informed practical decisions. What you are describing as "practical standards" here is just what I mean by context. You can't have knowledge in absense of a context-- to claim that there is some ethereal "final truth" that is only approximable is to advocate omniscience as a standard of knowledge. And that, of course, leads to skepticism.
Thanks for agreeing. This shows that I can know what I mean even if I have defined it erroneously or improperly communicated my meaning and that meaning comes before definition. Moreover, it is only by being empirically motivated (focusing on referents rather than definitions or concepts) that one widens the context. No, this shows that if you learn something that makes your current definition invalid, you have to go through the trouble of making a new one that better encapsulates what you know about the referents in question. I was reading Rand yesterday, and she makes an important point that a definition is, in effect, a condensation of everything you know about the referents that you are seeking to describe, so naturally if you find something new, you might need a new (and better) definition. Of course meaning comes before definition-- I agree with you completely on that. As far as "empirical motivation", when did I argue otherwise? Only by examining the nature of the referents can you make a valid definition, and if you find something new, your definition may cease to be valid.
If I asked you whether Dagny Taggert died in Atlas Shrugged, you would say that she didn't. You know that the book is a work of fiction, but you would still say that it is it is TRUE that Dagny Taggert did not die. You would be willing to rely upon your understanding of the concepts (Dagny Taggert was a woman and she was alive at the end of the book) and other statements in the book to verify your claim. It's clear from the context what you mean by a person dying in either case, yes. Saying that Dagny Taggart died in real life doesn't make any sense, since Dagny is a fictional character.
However, if I asked you whether President Ronald Reagan was dead or not, you would say yes, he has died. In this case however, even though you think of the issue of life and death essentially the same way, the standard of proof revolves ultimately around realistic considerations, not just someone's ideas.
Be careful here-- if you want to argue about "perfect abstract ideas" versus "realistic empirical means", you could just as easily claim that you read the words of the pages of Atlas Shrugged to form the idea of Dagny in your imagination-- that's just as "empirical." To let you know, as a side note, the distinction between "pure ideas" and "empirical facts" is something called the Analytic/Synthetic dichotomy, which Objectivism rejects.
Glad you agree, but if someone assumed that I meant that Martians had to be aliens given that they almost always are in science fiction, he could very well assume that I was confusing him. And nothing of scientific significance rests on fighting over the definition as long as we can agree on the referents and make judgments about them. I'm just going by your definition. It's clear that in most contexts that people know that there aren't real Martians running around on Mars, so people incorporate that piece of knowledge into their definition to mean something like: "A hypothetical inhabitant of the planet Mars, especially as a stock fictional character." (dictionary.com) But if you were to define Martians in your way, it could very well refer to humans that have colonized Mars, which isn't a possibility in the forseeable future, at least.
How are we to agree on the referents if we don't have a definition? List them explicitly?
How did my definition, and not your interpretation of it, exclude them? Unless otherwise stated, a definition referring to something refers to it in reality. You have to make sure to note if your word refers to something imaginary.
If you really think it is meaningless, fine, but I think you are being dishonest. You know what meaning you intend to communicate when you make that statement and you know the kind of kind of person who takes offense at that meaning. I would advise you not to mix up "meaning" and "truth" if I didn't know that you know better.
The statement "God is the source of morality" (say), has several words in it. One of these words is "God", for which I have found no referent in reality. Therefore this statement is literally talking about nothing-- that's how I say that it's meaningless. The common definition of God is "A being conceived as the perfect, omnipotent, omniscient originator and ruler of the universe, the principal object of faith and worship in monotheistic religions." (dictionary.com), and I have recongnized that no referent in reality can satisfy this definition. If other people choose to believe that such a being exists (or can exist), that's their problem.
Nate
|
|