| | Robert, you wrote,
"Considering what Peikoff is alluding to (perhaps unconsciously) when he brings out that Dantean language, I am all the more inclined to agree with Kelley that he is committing the fallacy of the stolen concept: bringing moral condemnation to bear on someone who has made an allegedly premoral choice to die."
After looking at this a bit more carefully, Robert, I think that you (and Kelley) are correct here.
You continue, "More broadly, though, I agree with you that positing a premoral choice to live is not necessary for the Objectivist ethics--and that it weakens the arguments for the Objectivist ethics instead of strengthening them."
I will go further and say that a premoral choice to live is not ~consistent~ with the Objectivist ethics. And while I agree with Peikoff's conclusion, I now see that Kelley has a point: Peikoff himself is being inconsistent. For example, consider Peikoff's discussion in OPAR: "Existence, therefore, does demand of man a certain course, it does include the fact that he must act in a certain way - ~if~; if, that is, he chooses a certain goal... Morality is no more than a means to an end; it defines the causes we must enact if we are to attain a certain effect. Thus Ayn Rand's statement that the principle replacing duty in the Objectivist ethics is causality, in the form of the memorable Spanish proverb "God said: Take what you want and pay for it." He then adds, "If life is what you want, you must pay for ~it~, by accepting and practicing a code of rational behavior. Morality, too, is a must ;- if; it is the price of the choice to live. That choice itself, therefore, is not a moral choice; it precedes morality."
Later, Peikoff addresses the following objection to this view: "If the choice to live precedes morality...what is the status of someone who chooses ~not~ to live? Isn't the choice of suicide as legitimate as any other, so long as one acts on it? And if so, doesn't that mean that for Rand, too, as for Hume and Neitzsche, ethics, being the consequence of an arbitrary decision, is itself arbitrary?" His answer is as follows:
"[This objection seeks] to prove that values are arbitrary by citing a person who would commit suicide, not because of any tragic cause, but as a primary and an end-in-itself. The answer to this one is: no.
"A primary choice does not mean an "arbitrary," "whimsical," or "groundless" choice. There ~are~ grounds for a (certain) primary choice, and those grounds are reality..." He then goes on to say, "A man who would throw away his life without cause...would belong on the lowest rung of Hell. (p. 248)
I must apologize for not being sufficiently sensitive in my previous post to the full context of Peikoff's remarks, for it is now quite clear that he does indeed contradict himself, a contradiction which, unfortunately, no amount of exegetical parsing can resolve. To say that there "~are~ grounds for a (certain) primary choice," that "those grounds are reality" and that "a man who would throw away his life without cause...would belong on the lowest rung of Hell" is simply another way of saying that the primary choice ~is~ a moral choice, after all. There is no justification whatsoever for consigning a person who makes a pre-moral choice to the lowest rung of Hell, which is a moralistic metaphor if I ever heard one! I now see that Kelley was absolutely right in his criticism of Peikoff, and that Linz's original article made a valid and insightful point, after all.
I think that this contradiction stems in part from the fact that Rand wasn't as clear as she could have been in her article, "Causality versus Duty" wherein she makes her point about the conditional nature of morality. As I say, I do think that Peikoff is right about the wrongness of throwing away your life without cause, but this simply means that, contrary to his earlier remarks, the choice to live is not premoral.
In fact, I would go so far as to say that the concept of a premoral or pre-normative choice is incoherent. A choice presupposes a standard, which is an end or goal that the choice is intended to serve. One always chooses for a reason or a purpose. In that respect, one's choice is a means to an end. Insofar as the end is not an ultimate value, it can be evaluated by one that is an ultimate value. In the case of Objectivism, a person's ultimate end or "standard of value" in this context is his highest moral purpose, namely his own happiness. It is for the sake of that end or goal that he "ought" to make his choices. If he chooses death without a good reason - if he decides to commit suicide when happiness is still possible to him - then he has made an irrational or immoral choice. This is what Peikoff ends up saying in so many words without actually acknowledging it, because, of course, to acknowledge it would contradict his earlier point that the choice to live is not a moral choice on the grounds that it precedes morality. Well, if the choice to live is not a moral choice, then the choice to die cannot be immoral; it cannot be a choice that defies reality and merits consignment to the lowest rung of Hell.
- Bill
|
|