About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Forward one pageLast Page


Post 40

Friday, August 2, 2013 - 4:19pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Elliot, if you think that giving a child a time-out when they are hitting another child, or repeating a behavior that puts them in danger, like running into the street is evil, then you need to stop and look at how nutty your views are.
------------------
Why don't you try answering the point that Objectivism only allows defensive force, and you are advocating other force?
I believe I was very thorough in describing what I hold to be the proper, moral use of force. I believe my views coincide with Objectivism and would not be at odds with Rand. You have not given any explanation as to what I said is wrong and why.

My disagreement isn't with Objectivism, but using the word "defense" when "retaliation" is the appropriate term. If you believe that it is okay to fine some one in court if they are convicted of something, like theft, then you too want to use force for something that is NOT defense.

Post 41

Friday, August 2, 2013 - 4:56pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Punishment for spite isnt something many would line up behind. But death penalties for murderers serves at least two functions: 0% recidivism, and whatever amount of finite waveoff is achieved by the certainty of punishment and summary judgement for heinous crimes. The latter is icing on the cake. The state has a high burden of proof to convict someone of murder, but having met that burden, fry away.

Had Hitler lived, I wouldnt have been found among those protesting outside of his public drawing and quartering.

I'm certain of that.

Post 42

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 10:20amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,
Humans start out with the right to go where they wish as long as it doesn't constitute trespass. They have the freedom of movement. Locking someone up would be a violation of that freedom of movement, unless they had done something that changed their relationship to the rights they once had.
Okay, but you are making an assumption/contradiction at the outset -- about rights being absolute. Rights aren't absolutes in the abstract sense, they are absolute in the concrete sense.

The first sentence above is correct. You have the right of movement when that movement doesn't violate another's rights. It is an example of rights being absolute in a concrete sense -- one which includes actual people and actual boundaries, etc. (concrete cases in the world where real people exist together).

But the second sentence is an assumption that rights are absolute in the abstract sense -- i.e., one that doesn't include actual people and actual boundaries, but is, instead, unconstrained by reality. In this sense, it is a floating abstraction to generalize that all people, everywhere, and all the time (i.e., in any imaginable circumstance possible) have the freedom of movement.

So, you switched senses (from correct to incorrect), and that led you to the conclusion that the punishment of crime involves altering our relationship to rights -- so that you could, in one minute, have a relationship to your rights and then, in the next minute (and for as long as a judge or jury "declares"), you have a different kind of relationship to your rights. After a while, a judge or jury may declare that you have a different relationship to your rights again -- so you can then be set free.

On January 1, 2013, John Doe had the right to travel from his home in San Diego to Mexico City. On February 1, he is caught in the act of cashing a check he knows to be bad and confesses. By June 1, 2013, he has been convicted and locked up. He now has no right to go to Mexico City.
That's an actual, concrete case and will therefore be illuminating. Did John Doe have the right to travel to Mexico City (incidentally, the "kidnap capital of the world"!) while committing crimes? Does anyone, anywhere start out with a right to be a criminal and also a traveler -- at the same time, and in the same respect? Is there some abstract, absolute right to be a criminal -- so that restrictions from punishment necessarily infringe on the "previous" right to be free from such punishment?

I answer all these in the negative. Instead of being absolute in the abstract sense, rights are only absolute when you refrain from violating them in the first place. Like car insurance, rights will "cover" you in lawful situations -- but would not, say, cover you if you went on a rampage with your car, destroying people and property at will. No car insurance policy would cover your damages, and no individual right would swoop in to protect you from properly being punished for that.

Because that's not what rights are for.

Ed


Post 43

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 11:02amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Elliot, in Post 37, you wrote,
Also: hurting someone to deter future crimes can only possibly be legitimate if you're deterring his own future crimes (which requires, among other things, an argument that there's a significantly higher risk of him committing a future crime than a typical citizen doing so). (And also an argument the deterrence will be significantly effective. Otherwise it's just non-defensive force.) Using force against Bob to deter Joe, Sue and Peter from committing crimes is blatantly incompatible with individual rights and Objectivism.
Well, punishing someone for committing a crime (by incarcerating him for assault, say) would deter both the person himself and other would-be criminals from committing similar crimes. Of course, if you can't find the perpetrator, it would be wrong to punish someone who is innocent of the crime just in order to deter other would-be criminals, for as you say, that would indeed violate individual rights.

The point I was making is that punishing a criminal serves both to deter the criminal himself and also other would-be criminals by sending a message that this is what will happen to you if you commit this kind of crime. So in that respect it serves a two-fold purpose. Defensive force isn't just force used against a criminal at the time he is committing the crime. It also involves force used to defend other innocent people against that kind of crime by preventing the criminal from committing the same crime again now that he has indicated his willingness to commit the crime.

That act of prevention can take the form of denying him the opportunity to commit the crime again by keeping him behind bars for the duration of his sentence, as well as deterring him from committing the crime in the future after he is released from prison. Incarceration of existing criminals can also involve the defense of innocent people against would-be criminals who but for the imposition of such penalties would themselves be willing to commit that kind of crime.


Post 44

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 11:26amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

Here's how it can matter:

Definition of terms

Gilligan is a capitalist
Skipper is a socialist
Mary Ann is a capitalist
Ginger is a socialist
Professor is a capitalist
Mr. Howell is a socialist
Mrs. Howell is a capitalist

Situation

Gilligan produces something of value to trade. Skipper is a socialist and believes that Gilligan -- who has amassed some value for himself (to trade or whatever) -- is a rights violator and, therefore, either has no rights himself, or has an altered relation to rights wherein it is not improper to steal value from Gilligan. So he steals from Gilligan with impunity.

Mary Ann, witnessing Skipper's actions against Gilligan -- but also thinking that rights or the relation to rights change upon violation -- takes Skipper's loot. Ginger, upon witnessing Mary Ann ...

And this cycle doesn't stop until everybody starves to death in total, tribalistic-warfare destitution (so that's why it matters). It's playing out today before our very eyes. In the last Batman movie, it was said that it's okay to steal from thieves. In various "Occupy" movements, sometimes things are either stolen or vandalized.

We don't just have a culture of corruption today, we have a culture of the (irrational) justification of corruption. That's why my fine point matters.

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 8/03, 11:33am)


Post 45

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 11:32amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Mr. Howell is a socialist? But he was the millionaire!

Post 46

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 11:34amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Heh, in today's world, you can be a socialist millionaire (which is precisely the problem).

:-)


Post 47

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 11:36amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

I wrote:
Humans start out with the right to go where they wish as long as it doesn't constitute trespass. They have the freedom of movement. Locking someone up would be a violation of that freedom of movement, unless they had done something that changed their relationship to the rights they once had.
That was very poorly worded. You are correct that the first sentence is true. It is the second sentence where I must not have had my morning coffee. "Freedom," in this context, is that political condition where individual rights are protected. What I meant to speak about was not the political environment, but moral rights. I should have said, "They have the moral right to move freely," which is just restating that first sentence. My error was in using the word "freedom" ambiguously - shifting back and forth between speaking of rights versus environment.
-----------------

You wrote:
So, you switched senses (from correct to incorrect), and that led you to the conclusion that the punishment of crime involves altering our relationship to rights -- so that you could, in one minute, have a relationship to your rights and then, in the next minute (and for as long as a judge or jury "declares"), you have a different kind of relationship to your rights. After a while, a judge or jury may declare that you have a different relationship to your rights again -- so you can then be set free.
We still disagree. And you aren't understanding my position. I am saying that a person's moral right can change, but NOT due to the judge and jury. The laws, and the judge and the jury are societies attempt to have a legal system whose processes will safeguard our moral and legal rights. I'm saying that person A's moral rights can change ONLY due to Person A's choices. No one else can take away an individual's moral rights. We can honor them, or violate them. We can do this knowingly, or in ignorance of what we are doing in the moral realm. Only the individual can choose to step away from their own individual rights in some fashion or another, to some degree or another, and knowing what they are doing, or not.

You were correct in seeing that a judge or jury could effect someone's 'freedom' but, as you rightly point out, that is their concrete circumstance. That judge or jury may have made an appropriate judgment of the circumstances' facts, or of the relationship of the facts to the law, and the law may or may not be in correspondence with individual rights.
-------------------

You asked:
Does anyone, anywhere start out with a right to be a criminal and also a traveler -- at the same time, and in the same respect? Is there some abstract, absolute right to be a criminal -- so that restrictions from punishment necessarily infringe on the "previous" right to be free from such punishment?
Does anyone, anywhere start out with a right to be a criminal - lets take that first. The answer is "maybe" - depends upon whether or not the crime was a violation of an individual right. There can be no such thing as a right to violate a right because it would make nonsense of the term "right." So, if the crime involved initiating force, or theft or fraud, the answer is "No." If it was violation of the Clayton AntiTrust Act, the answer is "Yes, they had the right to commit that crime." But you asked a compound question - the second half was, "Does anyone, anywhere start out with the right to be traveler" and taken by itself, the answer is obviously, "Yes." So, if there is any validity to your view of rights and punishment, it is in this linkage between violating the rights of another and then traveling. I can find no such linkage anywhere in metaphysics, in the epistemological nature of the concepts we are discussing, or a compelling logicical argument for seeing rights and punishment in this fashion. To me it seems like a way of mentally modeling rights in the area of punishment that is less desirable.

What you have done, as best as I can see, is throw up a straw man argument that creates this bogey man - this alleged 'right to avoid punishment' and then you say that no such right exists. But no one is arguing in favor of a right to avoid punishment. Nor is it implied in an argument that says people can voluntarily relinquish rights and that is why punishment for a rights violation does not violate a right. The same approach is evident when you argue that there is no right to be a criminal. Who has argued for that? Certainly not me.

To make things simpler envision a desert island with a couple of people but no laws. On this island, you agree to limit your right to go where you want on the island, in exchange for something one of the others agrees to give you. Then have you not voluntarily stepped away from a portion of your individual rights? I say, "Yes" and that we can do that because, by their nature, we 'own' our rights, or more precisely, we 'own' the objects of our rights because that is what it means to say we have a right to something. And what we 'own' we can trade, give up, or assert ownership to.

A thug cannot violate the rights of another and still claim to have the right to avoid punishment. But it is the commission of the specific act of thuggery that brought punishment into view as a question, and it is the act of thuggery, which he CHOSE to commit, where he implicitly gave away a portion of his rights. Cause and effect. Until an act is committed, we can't know what punishment would be appropriate, that's because to be appropriate, it must match the decrease in the rights the violator has. And the decrease in his rights is proportional to the rights he violated.

Post 48

Saturday, August 3, 2013 - 12:05pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,
Gilligan produces something of value to trade. Skipper is a socialist and believes that Gilligan -- who has amassed some value for himself (to trade or whatever) -- is a rights violator and, therefore, either has no rights himself, or has an altered relation to rights wherein it is not improper to steal value from Gilligan. So he steals from Gilligan with impunity.
There errors here are rampant. Because someone 'believes' something doesn't make it right. What if I said, "Skipper believes he is a Nietzsche-like superman who is above morality and therefore it is okay for him to steal Gillgan's stuff"?

We both agree that should someone actually be a rights violator, then punishment is appropriate. That isn't where our disagreement exists. So, if Gilligan were a rights violator we would agree that an appropriate punishment was just. But your acts by the Skipper constitute a straw man that neither of us would see as a just or logical mechanism for judging guilt or administering justice.

Your terminology gives away the straw man nature of your example. You say "...not improper to steal..." but 'steal', by definition is wrong. If Gilligan had violated a right, and he were judged in an appropriate fashion, and then fined an appropriate amount, it would not be theft.

When you say, "...he steals from Gilligan with impunity" you are just creating a fantasy ending to your fantasy beginning. Skipper's fantasy of what he can or cannot do are the only impunity here. A psychopath can believe they are justified in their actions, and the wisest of men acting as judiciously as they know how can believe they are justified in their actions. In other words, so what?

If you believe that my understanding that an individual diminishes his moral rights by the violation of the rights of another is in any way a party to your description of today's corruption, then you need to think again!
-------------------

Gilligan produces something of value to trade. Skipper is a socialist and believes that Gilligan -- who has amassed some value for himself (to trade or whatever) -- is a rights violator and, because no one has the right to avoid punishment for their crimes, it is not improper to punish Gilligan by taking value from him. So he takes from Gilligan with a feeling of moral impunity.

I hope that you can see from that re-write of your example that the aspect of the relationship between bad acts and rights that we are disagreeing on is NOT going to make the great changes you imply. It is not a pivot on which socialism and capitalism swing. It will not be a deciding factor in the existence of corruption. And that you needed to take more care in your example.

Post 49

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 8:58amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

Thanks for the responses. I'll reply when I can ...


Post 50

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 2:21pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,
Does anyone, anywhere start out with a right to be a criminal - lets take that first. The answer is "maybe" - depends upon whether or not the crime was a violation of an individual right.
Okay, but let's get past the parsing of words. When I used the term "criminal", I meant "rights-violator." I wasn't entertaining the silly notion of the victimless crime. For the rest of this thread, when I say "crime" I mean "rights-violator."

If it was violation of the Clayton AntiTrust Act, the answer is ...
See above.

... if there is any validity to your view of rights and punishment, it is in this linkage between violating the rights of another and then traveling. I can find no such linkage anywhere in metaphysics, in the epistemological nature of the concepts we are discussing, or a compelling logicical argument for seeing rights and punishment in this fashion. To me it seems like a way of mentally modeling rights in the area of punishment that is less desirable.
Steve, ??? You were saying that John Doe had started out on his trip with a right to travel to Mexico, but that he lost that right when he committed a crime (a rights-violation) -- something which allowed for him to be justly punished, effectively preventing him from travelling to Mexico, without inadvertently violating his rights.

I responded that there is another way that John could be prevented from travel to Mexico without inadvertently violating his rights -- i.e., that is, if he never actually had some kind of an abstract, free right to travel which was entirely disconnected from whether he violates others' rights or not.

A right that is disconnected from whether you violate others' rights or not, is an absolute in the abstract sense of the term -- it is absolutely absolute (rather than being contextually absolute). What you are saying is that we have this thing that is absolutely absolute -- immutable -- but that our actions impinge on it or at least alter our relation to it. What I'm saying is that there is a human purpose for rights that already constrains them -- and that they are not ratio-idealized, Plato-Kantian, free-of-context absolutes in the first place.

But no one is arguing in favor of a right to avoid punishment.
But isn't that the very right you claim you lose when you commit a crime? You may not be arguing for it to be a good thing to have such a right, but you seem to be arguing for it to be a metaphysical thing for you to have such a right (that is, until you forfeit it upon committing a crime).

On this island, you agree to limit your right to go where you want on the island, in exchange for something one of the others agrees to give you. Then have you not voluntarily stepped away from a portion of your individual rights? I say, "Yes" and that we can do that because, by their nature, we 'own' our rights, or more precisely, we 'own' the objects of our rights because that is what it means to say we have a right to something. And what we 'own' we can trade, give up, or assert ownership to.
This is thinking which can be inadvertently used by evil social contractarians (i.e., tyrants) in a devil's bargain of trading freedom for security. Ask people in N. Korea whether they feel like there's nothing they can do about tyranny -- because they thought that they were originally so metaphysically powerful that they could trade away their right to freedom for the promise of security and, therefore, can never get it back (because "a deal is a deal"). On this existentialist view of the matter, you are free to make any trades -- even ones that contradict your metaphysical nature as a human being.

Rand's answer was that you are "free" to want such things, but not "free" to have them (not "free" to succeed in reality -- by contradicting your identity as a human being).

But it is the commission of the specific act of thuggery that brought punishment into view as a question, and it is the act of thuggery, which he CHOSE to commit, where he implicitly gave away a portion of his rights. Cause and effect. Until an act is committed, we can't know what punishment would be appropriate, that's because to be appropriate, it must match the decrease in the rights the violator has. And the decrease in his rights is proportional to the rights he violated.
I agree. The theme of this debate is actually punishment, specifically how it is that rights relate to punishments.

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 8/04, 3:01pm)


Post 51

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 2:57pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

What if I said, "Skipper believes he is a Nietzsche-like superman who is above morality and therefore it is okay for him to steal Gillgan's stuff"?
:-) That made me laugh. But I want to verify that you see where I came from....

In the analogy, Skipper was looking at Gilligan through 2 lenses which, when combined, produced a moral sphere of action which included stealing from Gilligan. The first lens is the socialist lens, wherein any accumulation of private property is considered to be immoral, even criminal (because "property" is something which should only be publicly owned, not privately owned). So viewed through that one lens, Gilligan is immoral; even a rights-violator.

The second lens is the criminality-forfeits-rights lens. Adding it to the first leads you directly to the view that Gilligan is a creature with less than a full spectrum of rights (because of his overtly-capitalistic behaviors). Now, if you ever come across a creature or a species with less than a full spectrum of rights (e.g., say, for example, one called homo criminalis), then you can do things to that creature that you could not morally do to a creature in possession of such a full spectrum of rights. That's why it becomes fine to steal from Gilligan.

Mary Ann is in the same situation with the second lens, but substitutes a more objective morality of egoism/capitalism (which gets used against Skipper because his anti-capitalist actions contradict/violate that morality or ethic of behavior).

If Gilligan had violated a right, and he were judged in an appropriate fashion, and then fined an appropriate amount, it would not be theft.
I agree, and I think that the reason that it would not be theft might be the core of our debate -- but am not yet sure about that. Good stuff, though. This quote, in relation to our debate, makes me have that anticipation feeling you get when there is a word you are trying to remember, but it is just out of reach of your consciousness.

When you say, "...he steals from Gilligan with impunity" you are just creating a fantasy ending to your fantasy beginning. Skipper's fantasy of what he can or cannot do are the only impunity here. A psychopath can believe they are justified in their actions, and the wisest of men acting as judiciously as they know how can believe they are justified in their actions. In other words, so what?
See above (where I elaborate on the link between the actions of the cast-aways to how it is that rights were viewed).

... then you need to think again!
I most certainly do (and thanks for the reminder)!

:-)

We all need "to think again." This is because of our nature as the specific kind of creature that we are. It is not improper for us to run around telling each other that we need to think again. It's actually a sign that we respect the reasoning of other people (i.e., the inherent, unique-on-this-planet capacity for humans to actually get things right) -- when we tell them to think again. However, beware, too much of a good thing can be bad.

:-)

... because no one has the right to avoid punishment for their crimes, it is not improper to punish Gilligan by taking value from him. So he takes from Gilligan with a feeling of moral impunity.
Aha! There is that feeling again (like when a word is on the tip of your tongue). I think I've got the upper hand on this analogy, but that may need to be explored more. For instance, there is more leeway to do things to people, if those people forfeited their rights. This means that punishments could take many forms, even subjective and otherwise-random forms: theft, rape, torture, etc., as long as it was discovered to be proportionate to the original crime.

On my view, however -- where punished criminals still have all of their rights -- punishment has to be more objective than that.

Ed


Post 52

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 3:32pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,
I wasn't entertaining the silly notion of the victimless crime. For the rest of this thread, when I say "crime" I mean "rights-violator."
I understand that. But the fact is that crime is defined by laws and the laws may have absolutely nothing to do with moral rights. They are entirely different dimensions - the moral and the legal. And, you know that many people have accidentally mix up the two here on RoR. You would be better off to use the proper word or phrase.
---------
You [Steve] were saying that John Doe had started out on his trip with a right to travel to Mexico, but that he lost that right when he committed a crime (a rights-violation) -- something which allowed for him to be justly punished, effectively preventing him from travelling to Mexico, without inadvertently violating his rights.
John Doe had started his LIFE, not his trip, with the right to travel.... but otherwise, correct.
---------
I responded that there is another way that John could be prevented from travel to Mexico without inadvertently violating his rights -- i.e., that is, if he never actually had some kind of an abstract, free right to travel which was entirely disconnected from whether he violates others' rights or not.
And there is the problem. The man has the right to travel... UNTIL he violates the rights of others AND that specific right is, in a very specific fashion, denied. That is, following a conviction, his sentence is for six months. During that 6 months he has no right to travel. But ONLY that 6 months is effected, and this could only come about AFTER he violated rights, was arrested, was convicted and was sentenced.

You are misunderstanding my position if you think that there is NO connection between violating someone's rights and losing some rights of your own. Neither metaphysics, nor epistemology, nor morality can know the future in such as way as to block out the right to travel at that particular time in that particular person's life since they are not omniscient. There must be a sequence that goes like this:
  • It starts where the person first violates someones right.
  • Then we have the logical rule that there can be no such thing as the right to violate a right.
  • From that we can deduce that he stepped outside of his rights by the very act of violating another's rights.
  • Only at this point in time, at this stage of events, can the law have the information needed to determine a just punishment.
  • That is important, obviously, because a just punishment must not be too severe relative to the rights the criminal violated. If it is, the law is violating his rights.

-----------
What you are saying is that we have this thing that is absolutely absolute -- immutable -- but that our actions impinge on it or at least alter our relation to it.
No. I am staying inside of the context of what a moral right is. And we have, as part of the rights themselves and our volition, the ability to step away from them (i.e, we can violate the rights of another, but we can never say that we have the right to violate a right - in other words, we can step away from the realm of rights), and we can voluntarily surrender a particular right - as we do when we make a contract.
-----------
What I'm saying is that there is a human purpose for rights that already constrains them -- and that they are not ratio-idealized, Plato-Kantian, free-of-context absolutes in the first place.
Nothing I've said divorces human purpose from rights. The rest of what you wrote, in so far as it applies to me - just babble. Stick with addressing my words.
-----------
I said that no one is arguing in favor of a right to avoid punishment. You replied:
But isn't that the very right you claim you lose when you commit a crime? You may not be arguing for it to be a good thing to have such a right, but you seem to be arguing for it to be a metaphysical thing for you to have such a right (that is, until you forfeit it upon committing a crime).
No. Because the punishment did not arise until sentence was passed. And that didn't happen till AFTER the act of violating someone's rights occurred. You can't lose the right to avoid a punishment that hasn't even been handed down. As to the general statement, that one has the right to avoid any punishment under any circumstance, that is something that neither of us is arguing for. Before he committed the crime, John Doe had the right to travel to Mexico. Why? Because he had not violated someones rights, been convicted and sentenced. When his sentence is up, he will again have the right to travel to mexico. This is the proper flow of logic between the moral and the legal, where we attempt to discover what is moral, and then create the laws that define what is legal.
-----------

Your reaction to my example of an island was strange. You say that giving up the right to travel to some part of the island, in exchange for something you want more, could "be inadvertently used by evil social contractarians (i.e., tyrants) in a devil's bargain of trading freedom for security. Yes, and a hammer can be used as a murder weapon... but that is hardly the point. I'm talking about things people do all the time. Someone signs a non-compete clause as part of the sale of their business - they gave up something they had a right to do in exchange for something else. You rent your house to someone when you are on an extended vacation, and then come back early - you still can't move back into your own house because you gave up that right in consideration for the rental arrangement.

Nothing in what I wrote is a contradiction of our identity. No where do I contradict our nature as volitional beings who can make contracts. No where to I concoct or sanction any agreement where one person gives away the rights of another. No where am I arguing in favor of tyranny - those are very silly over-reachs on your part.

Post 53

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 4:08pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

I find that most of the time when a moral argument takes the form of looking through a lens of a socialist, or any lens that is essentially wrong, it becomes to easy to stray from what is right in the main thread of the argument. And that is what shows up in post 51 where after performing some sort of additive process on two invalid ways of looking at things, you end up saying:
Adding it to the first leads you directly to the view that Gilligan is a creature with less than a full spectrum of rights (because of his overtly-capitalistic behaviors). Now, if you ever come across a creature or a species with less than a full spectrum of rights (e.g., say, for example, one called homo criminalis), then you can do things to that creature that you could not morally do to a creature in possession of such a full spectrum of rights. That's why it becomes fine to steal from Gilligan.
Nope. it did not lead ME to that view. I, and other Objectivists, see that view as an error. All you are really saying, despite taking a very long way around, including a trip to an island in the distant past of TV-land, is that if one adheres to a moral code that doesn't recognize the full set of individual rights for an individual, you will be more likely to violate some of that fellows rights. That would be true of the socialists, but not of me, or my argument.
----------------
...there is more leeway to do things to people, if those people forfeited their rights. This means that punishments could take many forms, even subjective and otherwise-random forms: theft, rape, torture, etc., as long as it was discovered to be proportionate to the original crime. On my view, however -- where punished criminals still have all of their rights -- punishment has to be more objective than that.
Not so. I didn't say they forfeited ALL of their rights. I have always maintained that punishment must be appropriate or else it will violate their rights. I have always said that the degree to which they violated the victims rights is the measure of the degree to which they forfeited their own rights. I have always said that it is this precise mechanism of rights being lost by stepping away from them in a specific act of rights violations that not only justifies punishment, but guides us to the proper punishment - it is more objective.

On the contrary, where you say they have their full set of rights, we are left with either an extreme of you can't punish them at all because they still have their rights, or you say that you can punish them because from the beginning they didn't have the right to avoid punishment. But if that is the case, we have no strong logical connection to guide us in what is appropriate punishment. Did the person start off with no right to avoid having both hands cut off as punishment for shop lifting? Seriously! There is no moral to legal, rights to punishments, logical connection in your scheme because ALL punishments are on the table as long as there is a rights violation. I'm quite certain that if you do a careful job of trying to use your view to argue for such a logical connection, you'll end up with my view. :-)


Post 54

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 7:35pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

It may take some time to develop a serious answer to your last 2 posts, but in the meantime I would like to offer an unserious (though still somewhat sincere!) response to something you said:

... by their nature, we 'own' our rights, or more precisely, we 'own' the objects of our rights because that is what it means to say we have a right to something. And what we 'own' we can trade, give up, or assert ownership to.
But I have a bold analogy against that:

Husband
Honey, I'm home!

Wife
Hiiiii!

Husband
Where are the kids?

Wife
Oh, I sold them into slavery today.

Husband
No, seriously, where are they?

Wife
[silent, serious stare]

Husband
[realizing] Why did you do it?

Wife
Well, I heard about how people own their rights, or at least the objects of their rights, and how rights (or the objects of rights) are something you can trade, give up, or assert ownership to -- so I asserted the ownership to our kids. Parents, you see, are the custodians of their children and of their children's rights. When, say, a child in school gets beat up, the parents come in and argue for their child's rights (rather than the child doing the arguing). Parents are in charge, in possession, of the rights of the child.

Husband
But I loved Bob-a-Louie and Charlamayne ... they were such great kids!

Wife
I know, Dear, but we really needed the money and well ... it's not like rights are metaphysically inalienable, or something like that -- which would, therefore, protect infringements on your life solely by virtue of the specific kind of creature that you are! I mean, gimme' a break!

Husband
Well, I guess you're right. I guess rights can be traded, piece-meal and willy-nilly -- as long as the trade itself was free from coercion. I guess it's true that humans have that kind of power over metaphysics. It just makes me sad to lose my only kids, that's all.

Wife
Oh, don't be such a Debbie-downer. We'll have more kids when our financial situation improves! And hopefully we will be able to remain financially stable and to keep them -- because I am not about to go back and check my premises about whether rights can be traded away or not (even if the lives of my own loved ones are at stake).
:-)

Ed


Post 55

Sunday, August 4, 2013 - 10:36pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed, I'm sorry, but that wasn't even a good try. I expect better of you. Parents don't own their children, and they don't own the children's rights. Their obligation is protect the children's rights. I wrote reports that put a number of parents in jail when I worked for Los Angeles Child and Family services - for violating their children's rights.

I was clear in my post that no one can sell someone else's rights. I wrote, "No where to I concoct or sanction any agreement where one person gives away the rights of another." But you chose to ignore that. Why?

I gave the specific example of people being able to form contracts where they forego some of THEIR OWN rights. Like where I wrote, "Someone signs a non-compete clause as part of the sale of their business - they gave up something they had a right to do in exchange for something else. You rent your house to someone when you are on an extended vacation, and then come back early - you still can't move back into your own house because you gave up that right in consideration for the rental arrangement." But you chose to ignore that. Why?

If you were being sincere you wouldn't have made up that little story as if my position was that people could violate the rights of others - that isn't an honest form of argument.

Post 56

Saturday, August 10, 2013 - 8:41amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Steve,

I agree it was a bad analogy. The problem is that there are 2 things (legal vs. moral rights) being talked about, and we haven't always been real clear about which one we've been using (which results in mind-boggling equivalence). So, when you said:
... by their nature, we 'own' our rights, or more precisely, we 'own' the objects of our rights because that is what it means to say we have a right to something. And what we 'own' we can trade, give up, or assert ownership to.
... you were talking about having a right to something, which is different from having the right to anything.


You shouldn't have brought up having a right to something, because that is not what we were talking about (we were talking about having the right to anything). Also, I shouldn't have added to the confusion by assuming, seriously or not, that a right to something (legal) is akin to the right to anything (moral). So, contrary to the purpose of the analogy, I actually agree with you that we can trade things which we have a right to own. But where I see disagreement is over whether we could ever trade rights, per se.

For instance, if it wasn't about kids but about adults, could they trade away their right to freedom? I answer "no." Humans do not have it in their power of choice to do that. The reason I say that is because I already have an answer to the question of whether rights are man-made or metaphysical. We can change things that are man-made, but we cannot ever change things that are metaphysical. Therefore, you cannot by personal choice trade, or by person action forfeit, your rights.

Ed

(Edited by Ed Thompson on 8/10, 8:48am)


Sanction: 6, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 6, No Sanction: 0
Post 57

Saturday, August 10, 2013 - 10:12amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I think you guys are arguing at cross purposes.

Clearly, Steve is correct in saying that one can give up one's property by exchanging it for something else. But Ed is not disputing that. I believe that what he is saying is that one cannot give up one's property rights as such, because the very act of giving up a piece of property in exchange for something else is itself an exercise of one's right to the property.

Property rights imply the right to use and disposal, and by exchanging one's property for something else, one is disposing of it according to one's wishes. One couldn't exchange it for something else if one didn't have the right to it to begin with.

So the right to surrender one's property is only possible if one possesses property rights in the first place -- if one possesses the right to control that which one owns. It is the right to control that which one owns that one cannot give up or surrender. In other words, one cannot surrender one right to life, liberty or the pursuit of happiness; nor, in the sense described, can one surrender one's property rights.


Post 58

Saturday, August 10, 2013 - 11:19amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Bill,

I agree and, as is not uncommon, you said it better than I did.

:-)

Ed


Post 59

Saturday, August 10, 2013 - 12:25pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Ed,

I certainly appreciate the clarity and generosity in your reply. It makes me feel that we are giving each other the material out which we will hone better understandings of a critical subject.

I'm not clear as to the differences you are ascribing when you contrast having a right to something with having the right to anything. You wrote, "...that a right to something (legal) is akin to the right to anything (moral)." There are a number of differences between moral and legal rights, but I don't understand making that distinction. If I worked, engaging in voluntary associations, earned some money and used the money to purchase a car - all voluntary, free market actions, then I have a right to possess or dispose of that car. It also works to say that I have the right to possess or dispose of that car. Note that the only conditions I've stipulated are those required to ensure that my right is moral (voluntary associations and productive effort). If I wanted to talk about a legal rights, I would have said that I SHOULD have a/the legal right to possess or dispose of the car. I said, "should" because the law is man made and may or may not coincide with our individual rights.

When we apply a moral or legal right to a concrete situation, we go from the general to the specific, of course. So, when I say that I have the moral right to posess or dispose of that which is mine, I'm still talking about my right in general. To apply it, I'll have to be specific, and I might say something like, "I'm selling my car to Bob." Once that sale takes place, I'll still have the right to dispose of my property, but that car will no longer be my property so, I won't have the right to dispose of it.

If we were to say that moral rights, because they are universal and stated, and understood, in those general terms that belong to all of us equally and inalienably, don't exist in any concrete form... that is, in application to a specific instance, then we would have torn them from reality and made floating abstractions of them. We have to be able to say, that if X is my property (acquired morally, regardless of the law of the particular nation), then I have the right to dispose of X. Once I have disposed of X, I no longer have the same moral rights to X that I did. I still retain my rights in general, because I have not done away with them. I only did away with the rights pertaining to X.

Rights should be understood as a collection of actions associated with something. I have the right to sell a car, to store it in my garage, to drive it, to loan it to friend, or to rent it out. If I rent it, I loose the right to drive or possess it for the period it is rented. Someone might say that these are legal rights - arising out of a contract - and that would be true, if it occurs in a nation whose laws recognize and support such things. But legal and moral can coincide. I can have a legal right to drive my car, and a moral right to drive my car.

You appear to be saying that we can separate out rights such that some can be given up (the legal ones?), and others we can not give up (the moral ones?). Am I getting that right? If that is your understanding, I disagree. If we own it, if it is ours, if we have it by moral right, then we can dispose of it. But we can only do so for ourselves, and our act cannot effect that right as held by others.

Someone might say that we don't have the right to sell ourselves into slavery. I find the idea of a 'voluntary slavery,' i.e., a contracted state of slavery, to be repulsive (technically, it can't really exist, since it can't meet the definition of 'voluntary' and 'slavery' at the same time - but ignore that for sake of argument). It might not be good for society and I believe that a society where such a thing happened to any degree would suffer for it. But the same could be said for a society that allowed socialist communes, as long as they were voluntary. The same thing could be said for a society that permitted people to get on a soapbox and pledge allegiance to Nazi ideals. But, if people have a right, they have a right.

Can a person trade away their right to freedom, per se? In one sense, "No." They can't 'trade away' their metaphysical nature, or the freedom of others. But there is no single, or set of single applications of that freedom that they can't trade away. If it can be enumeratred, listed, described, or just understood between the two parties, then it can be traded. And because it is silly to discuss a freedom where such a freedom can only be understood as long as it does not apply to anything specific... well, you get the idea.
----------------------

Bill,
In other words, one cannot surrender one['s] right to life, liberty or the pursuit of happiness; nor, in the sense described, can one surrender one's property rights.
I would agree that one cannot change the metaphysical nature of a human. I would agree that one cannot surrender what one does not own (like the rights of some third party). But I would argue that one can trade away anything that is theirs and can be part of a voluntary agreement. To be part of an agreement, it must be understandable, the understanding must be held by both parties, it must be voluntary, etc. - these are the moral conditions from which we have derived some of the elements of contract law.

That said, it means that there must be a clear understanding of what is being traded. And I'm saying that if that can be achieved, it can be traded. If it can't, then maybe not. But the deeper principle is that if we own something, we can either exercise or dispose of it.

Let's say a man is dying of liver cancer but has a good heart and he is a very rare blood type. Does he have the right to sell his heart, to earn money to leave his family, even though it means ending his life a few months early? Bill, I agree with you that if he didn't FIRST possess the right to his body, the right to his life, the right to trade away whatever he owns, he couldn't dispose of them. But if makes this deal, accepts the money and disposes of that, can he back out of his deal? Can he claim that it would violate some right that can never be taken from him, or given away? Clearly, ending his life will end every single right he ever possessed. If the contract were fulfilled, against the man's later change of mind, and his life taken to harvest the heart he sold, was that a violation of any of his rights? And if not, then a person can trade away their most basic of rights (but only their own, not for anyone else).

If I own a car, I can sell it. Or, going smaller, I can sell just a part of it (lease or rent it). If I own a business, I can sell the business. Or, going larger, I can sell, along with the business, my future rights to engage in that kind of business. The degree to which one can generalize or understand any right, while still being able to distinguish future acts that might come under that generalization or understanding, is a limit to what can be traded. This is just about the requirements that exist to have the 'meeting of the minds' that is the nature of a voluntary agreement.

Look at all that a person trades away when they join our voluntary military forces. It is pretty much every detail of how they live their lives for the next four years: what time of day they get up, what clothes they wear, what they eat, where they go, what they do, even - and in particular - the right to avoid dangerous situations that might leave them dead or maimed. The understanding shared by the military and the potential recruit is adequate in terms of what is being traded.

No matter how much we discuss this or that aspect of rights in the abstract, rights can have little effect on human life until an otherwise abstract right gets tied to a concrete. Past, present or future acts have to be related to the otherwise floating abstraction of rights to be of use. If we can describe, with adequate specificity and clarity, some future act, then we may be able to associate it with a moral right. And if we can do that, then it becomes something, all else remaining equal, a person with that right can trade away.

Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1Page 2Page 3Page 4Page 5Page 6Forward one pageLast Page


User ID Password or create a free account.