| | Bill, We both agree that you cannot give up your right to control that which you own while maintaining ownership of it. You can give up your right to control it only by surrendering ownership of it. In other words, you cannot own something yet have no right to control it. That is what I meant when I said that you cannot give up your right to property, because your right to property just is the right to control that which you own. I would phrase things a tiny bit difference, but you are right that we agree here. I'd say that "ownership" is about a bundle of rights. And that "property" which is commonly used to refer to a thing, like a car, or intellectual property rights to a specific work, is also better understood as a bundle of rights. And these bundles of rights are the kind of control (actions) that have moral sanction.
There is no such thing as a right that one could surrender, even if they "own" it, without first defining it adequately, and concretely, such that there can be a meeting of the minds (with one exception, and I'll get to that below - criminal acts). I think that this distinction is important in the ways we appear to be talking past one another. When you say that a person can't give up his Liberty, I'm torn between saying, "Yes" and saying, "No" - but not for the reason you give. I'm thinking of how could a person define the concretes of Liberty adequately such that it could be a part of a voluntary meeting of the mind.
We know that we have property rights - moral property rights - and we agree on how they arise in metaphysics and their place in a social context. But that is a very general, and abstract definition of a very large bundle of potential actions that would be morally sanctioned. Right now, ARI is receiving very specific royalty payments for the sales of Atlas Shrugged as a result of Ayn Rand's intellectual work in creating the 'property' and the agreements that conveyed those rights to her heir, and that define the particulars right down to the single copy. The right to print and sell copies of AS are restricted to a publisher - they were surrendered to the publisher(s) and once surrendered cannot at the same time be exercised. All of this is well covered in contract law, but it is supported by a moral foundation. ------ In short, it's impossible to give up your individual rights, because to give up your individual rights is allow someone else to initiate force against you, but even the act of agreeing to place yourself in the arbitrary control of another person is a voluntary choice. So any control that the other person exercises over you as a result of that choice is, by that very fact, not an initiation of force. Without admitting that you cannot give up your individual rights (under appropriate conditions), I have to concede that you are right about my examples. They are voluntary agreements by a person to be subject to specific acts of violence. That means the person chose them, and we presume a meeting of the minds and that puts them in a different category. They gave up their rights to not be hit in a specific context, but not their right to be free of initiated force in general. Bad examples - mea culpa.
But it still doesn't answer this question: "Is there any right that you can define as a specific action, or set of actions, that a person has a moral right to, that they can't then trade away?" If you stay extremely broad and say "Liberty" or "Individual Rights" or "Property Rights" then you aren't being specific and that is a requirement of making a trade. I would certainly agree that no one can trade away the root concept in any of those because they are universal. But when you get specific and tie them to acts of a specific individual, that's different. When you say you can't give away what you don't own, then it implies being specific about what is owned before a deal could be structured. -----------
You quoted Ayn Rand: No man -- or group or society or government -- has the right to assume the role of a criminal and initiate the use of physical compulsion against any man. Men have the right to use physical force only in retaliation and only against those who initiate its use. And I agree. The question is how do we avoid the logical conundrum of such a thing as a right to violate a right. There can be no such thing. When we lock up the convicted murder there is no question but that he no longer has the freedoms of action he had before we locked him up - very specific moral rights are no longer his.
Ed answers this by saying (and he can correct me if I'm getting it wrong), that the murderer never did have a right to be free of punishment for acts that involve the initiation of violence. But, at the same time, that he never has lost any of his individual rights from the act of committing murder (because murder was never an individual right). It is certainly not an unreasonable way to view moral rights. But I disagreed since that way of viewing rights doesn't give any way to justify the specific punishment for the specific crime. Why would life in prison be appropriate but 6 months probation not be? The answer here has to be not just some rationalizing about best for society, or eye for an eye, what ever works. It has to be an answer to the question, "What rights did the criminal surrender by the nature of act?" Those will define the limits of what the state can do to him. It must be seen that the murderer voluntarily abandon's his moral rights in the act of violence, and in the proportion of violence. This view of rights ensures that good law doesn't go to far with punishment. With Ed's position, the matter of the specifics of the choice the murder made is separate from specific rights. I can say that because Ed can't say where he looks to find out a rational AND moral degree of punishment. It is anything or everything because it is called punishment which is 'said' to be a kind of force that can be used - Yeah, but how much?
A related problem with Ed's view is about how to bridge the divide between my right to trade a fish I caught, for someone else's coconuts (the old desert island and no government context). We agree that we have individual rights, and even if we agreed that there is no way they are 'owned' such that they could be traded away in toto, how do we end up with specific moral rights that can be surrendered? People try to say one is moral (individual rights) and the other is legal. - No, because all actions in a social context are subject to moral judgment.
I say that the murderer surrenders moral sanction, to the degree that he initiates violence. The worse the crime, the more leeway the state has to punish without fear of violating rights the criminal might still hold. And therefore he no longer possesses the right to be free. For example, it is morally right to punish a young person that shoplifts a copy of Playboy magazine, but not with an execution or life in prison. It is the degree to which the criminal act is violating the rights of another, that tells us the kind and amount of specific moral rights the criminal has surrendered by their voluntary criminal choice.
From my perspective we can give up any right, moral or legal, under the proper conditions. In economic trades, the conditions include the definition of what acts to which moral and/or legal sanction is being traded away. In the initiation of violence, it is seen as a proportional response by government will keep society within its moral rights to protect, to retaliate, to establish justice, and not go to far, or not far enough. Both are instances where the person had a moral right till they voluntarily surrendered it (by making a trade, or by initiating force). ----------
So, when you say: ... I said that even the act of agreeing to place yourself in the arbitrary control of another person is a voluntary choice. So any control that the other person exercises over you as a result of that choice is, by that very fact, not an initiation of force. We agree on that. Commit a crime involving initiation of force, fraud or theft... you voluntarily surrender moral rights. Trade away some freedom of actions you had before (when you join the military, play football, rent out your house, etc.) and you surrender those specific moral rights (as defined, for the period defined). All cases of choice, and as you said, "not an initiation of force". My examples were flawed, but I still adhere to the principle that rights can be voluntarily surrendered if defined, either by criminal acts taken voluntarily, or by trades where the actions are adequately defined (meeting of the minds). (Note that the law doesn't punish someone for a criminal act that was not voluntary - insanity or under duress - the law recognizes that choice is required before a moral right is lost.)
|
|