| | Bill,
You wrote, One cannot trade away one's property rights, understood as the right to dispose of one's property according to one's judgment. In that sense, property rights are unalienable. Unalienable might be understood in that fashion, but you would have to make an argument for it. It make more sense from the Objectivist understanding of individual rights to see "unalienable" as meaning that they cannot be taken away. In Ayn Rand's on-line Lexicon she has an entry for "inalienability" which is clearly about violation, and nothing about not being able to trade away or voluntarily forego. Your use of the word "unalienable" doesn't settle the argument since it would have to be justified in itself as going beyond meaning rights should never be violated. ----------
Next, I just realized that "the right to control" as we are discussing it, IS ownership and ownership IS the right to control (use, dispose, etc.).
Ayn Rand's definition: A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man’s freedom of action in a social context." The two parts of the moral principle are the defining, and the sanctioning. The sanctioning is the statement of an actions rightness. The defining is where action is described.
Property, properly understood, is not just an object, but carries an implication of ownership as well (e.g., an object that is or can be owned). And ownership is the possession of a bundle of moral sanctions of actions regarding the object.
I think you are attempting to assert a 'right to control' without ever having any connection to any object. (More on this later). -----------------
This is just a quibble. Regarding my example of the man who makes a contract to sell his heart (he has terminal liver cancer and only a few months to live and wants die early if it enables him to earn the money to leave his family), you said, "...ending his life doesn't end his rights, because you can only end a person's rights, if he exists to possess them." Actually, you can only violate his rights while he is alive. And, he can only voluntarily surrender any right that can be surrendered, while he is alive. But once he is dead, he no longer has any rights. I didn't say that the ending of his life, in this strange example, was a violation of his rights, but that once he no longer existed, his rights no longer existed.
We agree that fulfilling the contract did not violate his rights, even though it meant putting him to death against his will - because he had made a contract when he sold his heart, and in that contract he voluntarily surrendered his heart, and thereby, his life, and his right to his life. Ending his life ended his rights (his breathing, his awareness, his ownership of things, etc.) but that isn't the same as saying his right were violated. There are "endings" which are not violations. Going to a car example: A car can be taken from a person against their will - but it might not be a violation of their rights, as in a theft or robbery - because it might be the enforcement of a valid contract - as in a lawful repossession. ------------------
I created that strange example to indicate that we own our rights. That is really where I see you coming from. I agree with the tautology that we have a right to that which is ours by right. And that will always be so, because of the structure of the sentence. But it doesn't have any further meaning until you identify the object of the right. At that point, there is a thing that can be surrendered.
Rights with defined objects, like anything else we own, we can voluntarily surrender... as through trade. A woman has a right to terminate a pregnancy. She can choose to not have the abortion in exchange for some consideration (e.g., some childless couple offers her enough money to change her mind).
You disagreed with the idea that we can trade away a right. Referring to the man who sold his heart, you wrote: But if he has a right to life, doesn't his fulfilling the contract trade away that right? No, because to say that he has a right to life simply means that he has the right to control his life according to his own judgment, and in this particular case, he has decided, according to his own judgment, to trade away his life in exchange for money. In making that decision, he does not trade away his "right to life," because he does not trade away his right to control his life according to his own judgment, which is what the "right to life" means in this context. On the contrary, he exercises that right in the very act of agreeing to the contract. We agree that he had the right to sell his heart. And we agree for the same reason, "he has the right to control his life according to his own judgement".
But the man changes his mind later, and tries to get out of the contract (after disposing of the money he received). This change of mind he has is also his judgement. It is more recent. Perhaps it is held with more intensity. Perhaps he musters more convincing arguments to support his new position. But to no avail. What is different is that he no longer possesses the right to control this aspect of his life. It was a moral right (a moral sanction to a defined freedom of action) that he surrendered in a voluntary agreement. He still possess the right to control some other aspects of his life, but not this one.
If I can adequately define a freedom of action to which I possess moral sanction to exercise, then I can trade that. I can surrender it for consideration. --------------------
You wrote, "...one does not trade away one's rights; one exercises them." Actually, one does both. In the exercise of the right to trade away a right, a right is lost. But there may still be other rights left, and maybe even more rights are acquired than were lost. If I make a good business deal, it might increase the number or the quality of the freedom of actions to which I have moral sanction.
There is an epistemological, or logical, symmetry that is required in the descriptions of rights and their objects. If I talk about the right to control, I have an obligation to indicate what the context is - what is being controlled. If I say that I have a right to control all things, that would obliterate the universal nature of individual rights, because it would be a claim to control things that others own. It would be a claim to have a right to violate a right, and therefore not logical. If I say I have a right to control that which I own, I am only saying that property rights exist. It doesn't change the ability to trade away rights in a defined object.
I am left viewing your statement that "One cannot trade away one's property rights, understood as the right to dispose of one's property according to one's judgment" as really only being true in the sense that one can not trade away the concept of property rights such that it would not exist for anyone. But clearly one can trade away absolutely anything that can be adequately described such that it can be the object of the meeting of minds in a voluntary agreement - and that includes objects that are rights (moral sanctions of defined freedom of actions).
|
|