James, Jordan, Robert, Edward-- I truly wish I had more time to devote to this discussion. I want you to know that I appreciate your willingness to address my criticisms.
In regard to whether or not Robert’s essay endorses a form of subjectivism, I will offer these additional quotes:
While many people will sign on to a general statement of principles—or declare allegiance to some abstract philosophy—the actual meaning of those abstractions is determined by the concrete, specific positions that the group or its leaders proclaim day to day. And on these specific implications there are grounds for endless feuds.
Such conflicts multiply almost infinitely when an organization’s scope of interest incorporates not just one principle, but an entire philosophy, such as Objectivism. Every day, the group is compelled to issue statements and position papers on specific new issues. What is the Objectivist position on Iraq? On the NSA wiretaps? On preemptive strikes against nations harboring terrorists? Does the group agree with Ayn Rand’s position about homosexuality? About women Presidents? About libertarians? About anarchism? About Romantic music? Is there some boundary line between Ayn Rand’s philosophy, and her conclusions on such specific issues? Etc.
Those members or participants who disagree with the group’s official stand on any of these issues face a moral dilemma. Should they continue to participate, lending their money and support to propagate views they think are wrong? Or should they try to weigh and balance the overall good they think the group does, against the bad? Or should they try to take over the group, kicking out the present leadership and then imposing their interpretations on everyone else?
It’s easy to see why philosophical advocacy groups are so unstable, and characterized by chronic purges and palace coups. The underlying problem is that such groups are rooted in the following principle: that some people are to serve as philosophical spokespersons for others.
No mind can represent another—not philosophically. No two people will grasp all the implications of a complex, systematic philosophy in exactly the same way.
To escape the trap of orthodoxy, other ideological groups—such as libertarian and conservative advocacy organizations—have gone to the other extreme, and deliberately eschewed any systematic philosophy. But you don’t solve the problem of authoritarian dogma by sinking to vacuous subjectivism. The proper approach is to structure organizational projects in which a systematic philosophy may be advanced in ways that respect the independence and integrity of all participants.
One such structure is the educational forum. In a forum, the views expressed are solely those of their author, and not those of the group. This, incidentally, is the way that The Atlas Society in general, and the Summer Seminar in particular, have always been structured—and it’s the main reason, I believe, for their stability and success. Members are united by the basic principles of Objectivism, but remain free to openly express and debate a range of interpretations and differences. Because no one is assumed to be speaking for anyone but himself, no one feels any pressure to enforce a party line—or to submit to one.
As I stated previously, Robert misinterprets Ayn Rand’s distinction with respect to compromising on “concretes and particulars” and extends it to apply to concrete, specific positions which involve fundamental principles—e.g., the Iraq war, preemptive strikes and anarchism. The other specific issues he mentions—homosexuality, government wiretaps, female presidents, libertarians, tastes in music—are sufficiently concrete and/or complex as to allow for reasonable debate from an Objectivist perspective. They do not involve fundamental tenets or their derivative principles.
The rest of the above cited quotations, taken in the context of the prior reference to the fact that “everyone who seizes upon Ayn Rand’s system…reads diverse meanings into her words,” imply that those individual interpretations are, at least to some extent, equally valid. To say that the only way to resolve such differences is through “orthodoxy” or the authoritarianism of a “spokesperson,” rather than a given thinker’s ability to defend their position through logic and reason, is, once again, subjectivism by implication.
For the record, I agree that ARI tends to support an attitude of “orthodoxy” in certain of the positions adopted by its intellectual leadership. However, the “orthodoxy” of which I disapprove has specifically to do with concretes that are not related to any fundamental or derivative principles, but to their unthinking idolatry of Ayn Rand and their blind condemnation of the Brandens, David Kelley, et. al. To describe ARI’s well-defended positions on most philosophical fundamentals and derivatives as “the trap of orthodoxy” is to blur the distinction between the rational and the arbitrary. I certainly would not deny that there is some room for legitimate debate here as well--particularly with respect to epistemology and esthetics--but those areas are much more delimited than what Robert seems to imply.
I had previously seen and read most of the various TAS commentaries cited by both Robert and Edward Hudgins. Although they generally make the case for the irrationality and destructiveness of Islamic fundamentalism, they most certainly do not address the critical issue of America’s right to use whatever force is necessary to win the global war on Islamo-fascism. It is possible I missed something, but I doubt it. For the most part, TAS’ is on record as supporting America’s current policy toward Iraq, giving implicit sanction to the monstrous sacrifice of over 2500 American soldier’s lives in the name of minimizing “innocent” civilian casualties.
This comes as no surprise, since TAS’ original “Position Statement” on the terror war called for doing everything reasonable to minimize civilian casualties in order to convince the enemy that our heart is in the right place, and it was accompanied by Patrick Stephens’ wringing endorsement of “Just War Theory,” in which he applauded the “heroic” sacrifice of our innocent soldiers to save enemy civilians.
In answer to James: I completely agree with Yaron Brook. Although I am not in a position to endorse specific military strategies, to risk the loss of thousands of American lives in order to save enemy civilians is a moral atrocity. That is precisely what we are doing by hamstringing our military’s ability to destroy Al Quaeda’s leadership.
I noted several articles on Robert’s blog in which he appears to give explicit support to Bush’s altruistic approach to conducting this war. The one positive thing I had not seen before was Robert’s criticism of Bush’s foolish and tragic efforts at ‘democracy-building’ in that Middle Eastern garbage dump. The fact that both Robert and Edward seem to regard Bush’s policy as consistent with America’s moral right to use the full force of her military might in this global conflict only underscores my position.
Either the TAS leadership has no understanding of the meaning of rational self-interest as applied to foreign policy, or they refrain from taking such a position as a concession to those ‘Objectivists’ who might disagree. I cannot believe that they do not see the difference between their stand and the morally consistent position taken by ARI. Robert’s essay suggests an explanation as to why they do not express it. Dennis
(Edited by Dennis Hardin on 7/25, 1:56am)
(Edited by Dennis Hardin on 7/25, 1:59am)
|